Why can’t you reassign the ‘mystery number’ in Cantor’s diagonal argument to a new number in the...












4












$begingroup$


I don’t want to claim that I have ‘refuted Cantor’ or something here, I just want to understand it adequately.
I do understand that the proof works something like this:
You assume that you can map the naturals onto the real numbers like so, where each letter represents some arbitrary digit:



$$1 — 0.abcdcdots$$
$$2 — 0.efghcdots$$
$$3 — 0.ijklcdots$$



And then you constrict the ‘mystery number’ $x$ which differs in at least one digit of each number that is assigned to a natural number. This mystery number, by definition, cannot be mapped onto any of the natural numbers. This is fine, but why can’t you just assign $0.abcdcdots$ to $2, 0.efghcdots$ to $3$, and so on, then assign $x$ to $1$, which would now be open?



What is the problem with doing this?



Update: Sorry for the poor notation and formatting, I’m writing this on my phone.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 9




    $begingroup$
    Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
    $endgroup$
    – Cheerful Parsnip
    Jan 18 at 2:57










  • $begingroup$
    Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
    $endgroup$
    – dantopa
    Jan 18 at 3:00






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
    $endgroup$
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Jan 18 at 3:12






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 18 at 4:53










  • $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Jan 20 at 18:28
















4












$begingroup$


I don’t want to claim that I have ‘refuted Cantor’ or something here, I just want to understand it adequately.
I do understand that the proof works something like this:
You assume that you can map the naturals onto the real numbers like so, where each letter represents some arbitrary digit:



$$1 — 0.abcdcdots$$
$$2 — 0.efghcdots$$
$$3 — 0.ijklcdots$$



And then you constrict the ‘mystery number’ $x$ which differs in at least one digit of each number that is assigned to a natural number. This mystery number, by definition, cannot be mapped onto any of the natural numbers. This is fine, but why can’t you just assign $0.abcdcdots$ to $2, 0.efghcdots$ to $3$, and so on, then assign $x$ to $1$, which would now be open?



What is the problem with doing this?



Update: Sorry for the poor notation and formatting, I’m writing this on my phone.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 9




    $begingroup$
    Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
    $endgroup$
    – Cheerful Parsnip
    Jan 18 at 2:57










  • $begingroup$
    Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
    $endgroup$
    – dantopa
    Jan 18 at 3:00






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
    $endgroup$
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Jan 18 at 3:12






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 18 at 4:53










  • $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Jan 20 at 18:28














4












4








4





$begingroup$


I don’t want to claim that I have ‘refuted Cantor’ or something here, I just want to understand it adequately.
I do understand that the proof works something like this:
You assume that you can map the naturals onto the real numbers like so, where each letter represents some arbitrary digit:



$$1 — 0.abcdcdots$$
$$2 — 0.efghcdots$$
$$3 — 0.ijklcdots$$



And then you constrict the ‘mystery number’ $x$ which differs in at least one digit of each number that is assigned to a natural number. This mystery number, by definition, cannot be mapped onto any of the natural numbers. This is fine, but why can’t you just assign $0.abcdcdots$ to $2, 0.efghcdots$ to $3$, and so on, then assign $x$ to $1$, which would now be open?



What is the problem with doing this?



Update: Sorry for the poor notation and formatting, I’m writing this on my phone.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I don’t want to claim that I have ‘refuted Cantor’ or something here, I just want to understand it adequately.
I do understand that the proof works something like this:
You assume that you can map the naturals onto the real numbers like so, where each letter represents some arbitrary digit:



$$1 — 0.abcdcdots$$
$$2 — 0.efghcdots$$
$$3 — 0.ijklcdots$$



And then you constrict the ‘mystery number’ $x$ which differs in at least one digit of each number that is assigned to a natural number. This mystery number, by definition, cannot be mapped onto any of the natural numbers. This is fine, but why can’t you just assign $0.abcdcdots$ to $2, 0.efghcdots$ to $3$, and so on, then assign $x$ to $1$, which would now be open?



What is the problem with doing this?



Update: Sorry for the poor notation and formatting, I’m writing this on my phone.







elementary-set-theory infinity






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jan 18 at 3:45









Andrés E. Caicedo

65.5k8159250




65.5k8159250










asked Jan 18 at 2:52









Caleb MahlenCaleb Mahlen

262




262








  • 9




    $begingroup$
    Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
    $endgroup$
    – Cheerful Parsnip
    Jan 18 at 2:57










  • $begingroup$
    Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
    $endgroup$
    – dantopa
    Jan 18 at 3:00






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
    $endgroup$
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Jan 18 at 3:12






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 18 at 4:53










  • $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Jan 20 at 18:28














  • 9




    $begingroup$
    Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
    $endgroup$
    – Cheerful Parsnip
    Jan 18 at 2:57










  • $begingroup$
    Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
    $endgroup$
    – dantopa
    Jan 18 at 3:00






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
    $endgroup$
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Jan 18 at 3:12






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 18 at 4:53










  • $begingroup$
    The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Jan 20 at 18:28








9




9




$begingroup$
Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
$endgroup$
– Cheerful Parsnip
Jan 18 at 2:57




$begingroup$
Sure you can accommodate a missing number on the list, but according to your assumption it was already there. That's the contradiction.
$endgroup$
– Cheerful Parsnip
Jan 18 at 2:57












$begingroup$
Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
$endgroup$
– dantopa
Jan 18 at 3:00




$begingroup$
Welcome to Mathematics Stack Exchange. Take the short tour to see how how to get the most from your time here. For typesetting equations we use MathJax.
$endgroup$
– dantopa
Jan 18 at 3:00




5




5




$begingroup$
Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
$endgroup$
– spaceisdarkgreen
Jan 18 at 3:12




$begingroup$
Sure, you can just add the real you constructed to the front of the list, but then you can construct another real, by the same method, that is not on your new list. The statement is "for any list of real numbers, there is a real not on that list" (i.e. there is no surjection $mathbb Nto mathbb R$). That is exactly what the diagonal argument shows, and your observation does nothing to refute that.
$endgroup$
– spaceisdarkgreen
Jan 18 at 3:12




1




1




$begingroup$
The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
$endgroup$
– Lord Shark the Unknown
Jan 18 at 4:53




$begingroup$
The diagonal argument doesn't assert that only one number is missing from the list.
$endgroup$
– Lord Shark the Unknown
Jan 18 at 4:53












$begingroup$
The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Jan 20 at 18:28




$begingroup$
The diagonal argument can be summarized like this: no matter what you do, no matter how you make your list, the list will be incomplete.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Jan 20 at 18:28










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















5












$begingroup$

Yes, if you are missing a real number, then you can always add it to the front of your list, but this not mean that the new list is now complete. (this is LordSharktheUnknown's point: if the mystery number was the only one that as missing, then yes, you'd get a complete list, but it may not be the only one missing).



In fact, we know the new list cannot be complete, because we can go through the same diagonalization to find a new mystery number that is not on this new list (this is spaceisdarkgreen's point)



And finally, remember that when you do the diagonalization on the original list, we did this within a proof by contradiction. That is, we assumed that there is a complete list ... but when we take any such supposedly complete list we can find a mystery number that is not on the list ... and so we reach a contradiction already. Coming up with a new list does not take away from the contradiction that you obtain when assuming there is a complete list at all, so you are doing nothing to refute the proof (and this is Cheerful Parsnip's point)






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$





















    0












    $begingroup$

    That is actually a valid question, but it is based on a misunderstanding of Cantor's Diagonal Proof. That is not your fault, it is taught incorrectly; usually something like this outline:




    1. For some infinite set T:

    2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces every element t in T.

    3. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

    4. (A) and (B) together prove that f(n) does not produce every element t in T.

    5. Since #4 contradicts the assumption in #2, that assumption must be false.


    The problem with this, is that to use Proof by Contradiction, you have to use every part of what you assumed to produce the contradiction. Any part you don't use isn't proven by the contradiction. All step #3 really uses, is that every f(n) is an element of T, not that every element of T is produced. So wondering if you can put it back in is a valid question. You can't, but to see why it helps to use Cantor's actual outline.




    1. For some infinite set T:

    2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces elements of T.

    3. The set of all elements produced by f(n) is the set S. Nothing is assumed at this point about whether S=T.

    4. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

    5. The two statement S=T and "There is a t0 that must be in T, but is different than every f(n)" can't both be true. Since we know that the second one is true, the first can't be.

    6. You can't count every element of T.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3077774%2fwhy-can-t-you-reassign-the-mystery-number-in-cantor-s-diagonal-argument-to-a-n%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes








      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      5












      $begingroup$

      Yes, if you are missing a real number, then you can always add it to the front of your list, but this not mean that the new list is now complete. (this is LordSharktheUnknown's point: if the mystery number was the only one that as missing, then yes, you'd get a complete list, but it may not be the only one missing).



      In fact, we know the new list cannot be complete, because we can go through the same diagonalization to find a new mystery number that is not on this new list (this is spaceisdarkgreen's point)



      And finally, remember that when you do the diagonalization on the original list, we did this within a proof by contradiction. That is, we assumed that there is a complete list ... but when we take any such supposedly complete list we can find a mystery number that is not on the list ... and so we reach a contradiction already. Coming up with a new list does not take away from the contradiction that you obtain when assuming there is a complete list at all, so you are doing nothing to refute the proof (and this is Cheerful Parsnip's point)






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$


















        5












        $begingroup$

        Yes, if you are missing a real number, then you can always add it to the front of your list, but this not mean that the new list is now complete. (this is LordSharktheUnknown's point: if the mystery number was the only one that as missing, then yes, you'd get a complete list, but it may not be the only one missing).



        In fact, we know the new list cannot be complete, because we can go through the same diagonalization to find a new mystery number that is not on this new list (this is spaceisdarkgreen's point)



        And finally, remember that when you do the diagonalization on the original list, we did this within a proof by contradiction. That is, we assumed that there is a complete list ... but when we take any such supposedly complete list we can find a mystery number that is not on the list ... and so we reach a contradiction already. Coming up with a new list does not take away from the contradiction that you obtain when assuming there is a complete list at all, so you are doing nothing to refute the proof (and this is Cheerful Parsnip's point)






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$
















          5












          5








          5





          $begingroup$

          Yes, if you are missing a real number, then you can always add it to the front of your list, but this not mean that the new list is now complete. (this is LordSharktheUnknown's point: if the mystery number was the only one that as missing, then yes, you'd get a complete list, but it may not be the only one missing).



          In fact, we know the new list cannot be complete, because we can go through the same diagonalization to find a new mystery number that is not on this new list (this is spaceisdarkgreen's point)



          And finally, remember that when you do the diagonalization on the original list, we did this within a proof by contradiction. That is, we assumed that there is a complete list ... but when we take any such supposedly complete list we can find a mystery number that is not on the list ... and so we reach a contradiction already. Coming up with a new list does not take away from the contradiction that you obtain when assuming there is a complete list at all, so you are doing nothing to refute the proof (and this is Cheerful Parsnip's point)






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          Yes, if you are missing a real number, then you can always add it to the front of your list, but this not mean that the new list is now complete. (this is LordSharktheUnknown's point: if the mystery number was the only one that as missing, then yes, you'd get a complete list, but it may not be the only one missing).



          In fact, we know the new list cannot be complete, because we can go through the same diagonalization to find a new mystery number that is not on this new list (this is spaceisdarkgreen's point)



          And finally, remember that when you do the diagonalization on the original list, we did this within a proof by contradiction. That is, we assumed that there is a complete list ... but when we take any such supposedly complete list we can find a mystery number that is not on the list ... and so we reach a contradiction already. Coming up with a new list does not take away from the contradiction that you obtain when assuming there is a complete list at all, so you are doing nothing to refute the proof (and this is Cheerful Parsnip's point)







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Jan 20 at 18:41

























          answered Jan 19 at 16:31









          Bram28Bram28

          63.2k44793




          63.2k44793























              0












              $begingroup$

              That is actually a valid question, but it is based on a misunderstanding of Cantor's Diagonal Proof. That is not your fault, it is taught incorrectly; usually something like this outline:




              1. For some infinite set T:

              2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces every element t in T.

              3. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

              4. (A) and (B) together prove that f(n) does not produce every element t in T.

              5. Since #4 contradicts the assumption in #2, that assumption must be false.


              The problem with this, is that to use Proof by Contradiction, you have to use every part of what you assumed to produce the contradiction. Any part you don't use isn't proven by the contradiction. All step #3 really uses, is that every f(n) is an element of T, not that every element of T is produced. So wondering if you can put it back in is a valid question. You can't, but to see why it helps to use Cantor's actual outline.




              1. For some infinite set T:

              2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces elements of T.

              3. The set of all elements produced by f(n) is the set S. Nothing is assumed at this point about whether S=T.

              4. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

              5. The two statement S=T and "There is a t0 that must be in T, but is different than every f(n)" can't both be true. Since we know that the second one is true, the first can't be.

              6. You can't count every element of T.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                0












                $begingroup$

                That is actually a valid question, but it is based on a misunderstanding of Cantor's Diagonal Proof. That is not your fault, it is taught incorrectly; usually something like this outline:




                1. For some infinite set T:

                2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces every element t in T.

                3. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                4. (A) and (B) together prove that f(n) does not produce every element t in T.

                5. Since #4 contradicts the assumption in #2, that assumption must be false.


                The problem with this, is that to use Proof by Contradiction, you have to use every part of what you assumed to produce the contradiction. Any part you don't use isn't proven by the contradiction. All step #3 really uses, is that every f(n) is an element of T, not that every element of T is produced. So wondering if you can put it back in is a valid question. You can't, but to see why it helps to use Cantor's actual outline.




                1. For some infinite set T:

                2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces elements of T.

                3. The set of all elements produced by f(n) is the set S. Nothing is assumed at this point about whether S=T.

                4. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                5. The two statement S=T and "There is a t0 that must be in T, but is different than every f(n)" can't both be true. Since we know that the second one is true, the first can't be.

                6. You can't count every element of T.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  0












                  0








                  0





                  $begingroup$

                  That is actually a valid question, but it is based on a misunderstanding of Cantor's Diagonal Proof. That is not your fault, it is taught incorrectly; usually something like this outline:




                  1. For some infinite set T:

                  2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces every element t in T.

                  3. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                  4. (A) and (B) together prove that f(n) does not produce every element t in T.

                  5. Since #4 contradicts the assumption in #2, that assumption must be false.


                  The problem with this, is that to use Proof by Contradiction, you have to use every part of what you assumed to produce the contradiction. Any part you don't use isn't proven by the contradiction. All step #3 really uses, is that every f(n) is an element of T, not that every element of T is produced. So wondering if you can put it back in is a valid question. You can't, but to see why it helps to use Cantor's actual outline.




                  1. For some infinite set T:

                  2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces elements of T.

                  3. The set of all elements produced by f(n) is the set S. Nothing is assumed at this point about whether S=T.

                  4. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                  5. The two statement S=T and "There is a t0 that must be in T, but is different than every f(n)" can't both be true. Since we know that the second one is true, the first can't be.

                  6. You can't count every element of T.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  That is actually a valid question, but it is based on a misunderstanding of Cantor's Diagonal Proof. That is not your fault, it is taught incorrectly; usually something like this outline:




                  1. For some infinite set T:

                  2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces every element t in T.

                  3. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                  4. (A) and (B) together prove that f(n) does not produce every element t in T.

                  5. Since #4 contradicts the assumption in #2, that assumption must be false.


                  The problem with this, is that to use Proof by Contradiction, you have to use every part of what you assumed to produce the contradiction. Any part you don't use isn't proven by the contradiction. All step #3 really uses, is that every f(n) is an element of T, not that every element of T is produced. So wondering if you can put it back in is a valid question. You can't, but to see why it helps to use Cantor's actual outline.




                  1. For some infinite set T:

                  2. Assume there is a mapping f(n), for n=1,2,3,..., that produces elements of T.

                  3. The set of all elements produced by f(n) is the set S. Nothing is assumed at this point about whether S=T.

                  4. Use Diagonalization to construct a new element t(0) that (A) must be in T, but (B) is different than every f(n).

                  5. The two statement S=T and "There is a t0 that must be in T, but is different than every f(n)" can't both be true. Since we know that the second one is true, the first can't be.

                  6. You can't count every element of T.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Jan 20 at 18:24









                  JeffJoJeffJo

                  1654




                  1654






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3077774%2fwhy-can-t-you-reassign-the-mystery-number-in-cantor-s-diagonal-argument-to-a-n%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

                      in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith

                      Npm cannot find a required file even through it is in the searched directory