Why is this true? $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
$begingroup$
Why is this true?
$(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
logic quantifiers predicate-logic
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Why is this true?
$(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
logic quantifiers predicate-logic
$endgroup$
4
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
1
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Why is this true?
$(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
logic quantifiers predicate-logic
$endgroup$
Why is this true?
$(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
logic quantifiers predicate-logic
logic quantifiers predicate-logic
edited Jun 17 '13 at 20:32
Peter Smith
40.6k340120
40.6k340120
asked Jun 5 '13 at 20:46
MatsMats
447510
447510
4
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
1
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56
add a comment |
4
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
1
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56
4
4
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
1
1
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56
add a comment |
11 Answers
11
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Since this may be homework, I do not want to provide the full formal proof, but I will share the informal justification. Classical first-order logic typically makes the assumption of existential import (i.e., that the domain of discourse is non-empty). In classical logic, the principle of excluded middle holds, i.e., that for any $phi$, either $phi$ or $lnotphi$ holds. Since I first encountered this kind of sentence where $P(x)$ was interpreted as "$x$ is a bird," I will use that in the following argument. Finally, recall that a material conditional $phi to psi$ is true if and only if either $phi$ is false or $psi$ is true.
By excluded middle, it is either true that everything is a bird, or that not everything is a bird. Let us consider these cases:
- If everything is a bird, then pick an arbitrary individual $x$, and note that the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird,” is true, since the consequent is true. Therefore, if everything is a bird, then there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
- If it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there must be some $x$ which is not a bird. Then consider the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird.” It is true because its antecedent, “$x$ is a bird,” is false. Therefore, if it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there is something (a non-bird, in fact) such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Since it holds in each of the exhaustive cases that there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird, we conclude that there is, in fact, something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Alternatives
Since questions about the domain came up in the comments, it seems worthwhile to consider the three preconditions to this argument: existential import (the domain is non-empty); excluded middle ($phi lor lnotphi$); and the material conditional ($(phi to psi) equiv (lnotphi lor psi)$). Each of these can be changed in a way that can affect the argument. This might not be the place to examine how each of these affects the argument, but we can at least give pointers to resources about the alternatives.
- Existential import asserts that the universe of discourse is non-empty. Free logics relax this constraint. If the universe of discourse were empty, it would seem that $exists x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ should be vacuously false.
Intuitionistic logics do not presume the excluded middle, in general. The argument above started with a claim of the form “either $phi$ or $lnotphi$.”- There are plenty of philosophical difficulties with the material conditional, especially as used to represent “if … then …” sentences in natural language. If we took the conditional to be a counterfactual, for instance, and so were considering the sentence “there is something such that if it were a bird (even if it is not actually a bird), then everything would be a bird,” it seems like it should no longer be provable.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Hint: The only way for $Aimplies B$ to be false is for $A$ to be true and $B$ to be false.
I don't think this is actually true unless you know your domain isn't empty. If your domain is empty, then $forall y: P(y)$ is true "vacuously," but $exists x: Q$ is not true for any $Q$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
The examples with birds or drinkers were designed to make this simple logical truth sound paradoxical. Perhaps an example from ordinary mathematics will dispel the air of paradox. Consider a nonempty set $X$ and a function $f:Xrightarrow{0,1}$. Does the following proposition seem strange and unintuitive?
Theorem. There is an element $min X$ such that, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $xin X$.
Proof. The function $f$ has an absolute minimum. (The domain is nonempty and the range is a finite set of numbers.) Let $m$ be a point in $X$ where $f$ attains its minimum value. Clearly, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $x$.
Really, all that logical formula is saying is that the truth value ($1$ for true, $0$ for false) of the "propositional function" $P(x)$ attains its minimum.
$endgroup$
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In classical logic the following equivalence is logically valid:
$$
exists x (varphiRightarrowpsi)Longleftrightarrow(forall xvarphiRightarrowpsi)
$$
providing that $x$ is a variable not free in $psi$. So the formula in question is logically equivalent to $forall xP(x)Rightarrowforall yP(y)$.
Looking at the poblem from a slightly different perspective. Either (i) all objects in the domain of discourse have property $P$, i.e. $forall y P(y)$ is true or (ii) there is $a$ in the domain for which $P$ fails, i.e. $neg P(a)$ is true. In (i) $P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, so $exists x(P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y))$ is true. In (ii) $P(a)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, therefore the sentence in question must be true as well.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In mathematics, if not in philosophy, the domain of quantification is usually made explicit in statements. If we let the domain be some set $U$, your statement becomes
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
or equivalently
$$exists x(xin U wedge (P(x) Rightarrow forall y(yin URightarrow P(y))))$$
Then you can formally prove this statement is true iff $U$ is non-empty as sketched here:
For non-empty $U$, consider two cases:
$$forall yin U (P(y))lor negforall yin U (P(y))$$
In each case, obtain
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
For empty U, assume to the contrary that
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
and obtain a contradiction.
Full text of formal proof at http://dcproof.com/Mats.htm
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's a different approach: this can be fairly-straightforwardly proved from simple boolean algebra, starting from a tautology.$quad$
$$
((forall y)P(y)) lor (lnot (forall x) P(x)) \
((forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)lnot P(x))\
(text{anything} Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow text{anything})) \
((forall x)P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))
$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The location of the parentheses is crucial here. Note that $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$ is very different from $(exists x)(P(x)) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$. To see why the former statement is true, consider its negation which is
$$forall x (P(x) wedge neg forall P(x)) equiv forall x(P(x) wedge exists x neg P(x))$$
which is clearly false if your domain is nonempty. In classical logic, we restrict to nonempty domains, so your original statement will always be true.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Translate it to english:
In any universe of things, there can always be found an instance which, if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
For any given property, you can find an instance in a set of things to make it true. (As long as that set is not the empty set, by the way; existential assertions are false for empty sets.)
If none of the things have the property, then you can choose any one of them. Call that chosen instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is vacuously true, because $P Rightarrow Q$ is true whenever $P$ is false.
If all of the things have the property, then you can also choose any of them to be the instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is then true because $P(a)$ is true, and $(forall y) P(y)$ is true.
If some things have the property but not others, then you just choose one which does not have the property to be the instance $a$. Then $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is, again, vacuously true on account of $P(a)$ being false.
But let's look at it by taking the contradiction and seeing where it leads: $neg(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, there cannot be found an instance such that if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
we can move the negative inside: $(forall x)neg(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, for every one of its elements, it is false that if a given property holds true of the element, then it holds for all other elements.
Then we can integrate the $neg$ into the formula by way of $neg (Q rightarrow P) = Q landneg P$ to arrive at: $(forall x)(P(x) landneg (forall y) P(y))$
But this asserts $P(x)$ for all $x$; i.e. that if we think of any property $P$, all things have that property! This is clearly absurd for any nonempty set; we can come up with all kinds of properties $P$ which holds only for some things in a set, or none at all.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To add a proof in Fitch style, natural deduction:
2 | |__________ ~Ex(Px -> VyPy) New Subproof for ~ Introduction
3 | | |________ Pa New Subproof for -> Introduction
4 | | | |_____b variable for Universal Introduction
5 | | | | |____ ~Pb New Subproof for ~ Introduction
6 | | | | | |__ Pb New Subproof for -> Introduction
7 | | | | | | _|_ 5,6 _|_ Introduction
8 | | | | | | VyPy 7 _|_ Elimination
. | | | | | <-------------------- end subpproof
9 | | | | | Pb -> VyPy 6-8 -> Introduction
10 | | | | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 9 Existentional Introduction
11 | | | | | _|_ 2,10 _|_ Introduction
.. | | | | <---------------------- end subpproof
12 | | | | ~~Pb 5-11 ~ Introduction
13 | | | | Pb 12 ~~ Elimination
.. | | | <------------------------ end subpproof
14 | | | VyPy 4-13 Universal Introduction
.. | | <-------------------------- end subpproof
15 | | Pa -> VyPy 3-14 -> Introduction
16 | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 15 Existentional Introduction
17 | | _|_ 2,16 _|_ Introduction
.. | <---------------------------- end subpproof
18 | ~~Ex(Px -> VyPy) 2-17 ~ Introduction
19 | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 18 ~~ Elimination
This is the shortest I managed, I don't think a shorter proof using the standard introduction and elimination rules exist
For explanation I compare this "paradox" with:
If the last person has left the room, all people have left the room.
Therefore
There is a person if he has left the room, all people have left the room.
The first statement is a truism , so how can the last statement not be one?
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$tag 1 exists x ; [P(x) Rightarrow forall y , P(y)]$
Claim: (1) is a tautology, since it leads to an equivalence chain that ends in a well-known tautology:
$tag 2 exists x ; [ neg P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)]$
$tag 3 exists x ; [ neg P(x)] , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 4 neg , forall x , P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 5 neg , [forall z , P(z)] , text{ or } , [forall z , P(z)]$
The equivalence chain ends with a tautology, so (1) must also be one.
We can go from (2) to (3) since the existential qualifier distributes over disjunction and $( exists x) (forall y) , P(y) equiv forall y , P(y) $.
In (5) the $[;]$ brackets were put around identical expressions. It was not necessary to change both $x$ and $y$ to $z$ - they both were 'quantified away' and can be viewed as just logical placeholders.
Finally, this paradox can be viewed as a contortion of counterexample logic. The only useful tautology is (3); you can replace the $text{or-disjunction}$ with $text{XOR}$ (exclusive or).
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here is a sequent calculus style proof:
------------ (Id)
P(y) |- P(y)
--------------------- (Weak Right)
P(y) |- P(y), ∀yP(y)
--------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(y), P(y)⇒∀yP(y)
------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- P(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
--------------------------- (∀ Right)
|- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------- (Weak Left)
P(z) |- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
-------------------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(z)⇒∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y)), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (Contr Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
It uses a multi-consequent sequent calculus, so possibly
cannot be reduced to intuitionistic logic. Also the
contraction structural rule shows that a substructural
logic would possibly not do. These speculations could
possibly substantiated by some non-classical logic model
theoretic considerations.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f412387%2fwhy-is-this-true-exists-xpx-rightarrow-forall-y-py%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
11 Answers
11
active
oldest
votes
11 Answers
11
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Since this may be homework, I do not want to provide the full formal proof, but I will share the informal justification. Classical first-order logic typically makes the assumption of existential import (i.e., that the domain of discourse is non-empty). In classical logic, the principle of excluded middle holds, i.e., that for any $phi$, either $phi$ or $lnotphi$ holds. Since I first encountered this kind of sentence where $P(x)$ was interpreted as "$x$ is a bird," I will use that in the following argument. Finally, recall that a material conditional $phi to psi$ is true if and only if either $phi$ is false or $psi$ is true.
By excluded middle, it is either true that everything is a bird, or that not everything is a bird. Let us consider these cases:
- If everything is a bird, then pick an arbitrary individual $x$, and note that the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird,” is true, since the consequent is true. Therefore, if everything is a bird, then there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
- If it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there must be some $x$ which is not a bird. Then consider the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird.” It is true because its antecedent, “$x$ is a bird,” is false. Therefore, if it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there is something (a non-bird, in fact) such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Since it holds in each of the exhaustive cases that there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird, we conclude that there is, in fact, something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Alternatives
Since questions about the domain came up in the comments, it seems worthwhile to consider the three preconditions to this argument: existential import (the domain is non-empty); excluded middle ($phi lor lnotphi$); and the material conditional ($(phi to psi) equiv (lnotphi lor psi)$). Each of these can be changed in a way that can affect the argument. This might not be the place to examine how each of these affects the argument, but we can at least give pointers to resources about the alternatives.
- Existential import asserts that the universe of discourse is non-empty. Free logics relax this constraint. If the universe of discourse were empty, it would seem that $exists x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ should be vacuously false.
Intuitionistic logics do not presume the excluded middle, in general. The argument above started with a claim of the form “either $phi$ or $lnotphi$.”- There are plenty of philosophical difficulties with the material conditional, especially as used to represent “if … then …” sentences in natural language. If we took the conditional to be a counterfactual, for instance, and so were considering the sentence “there is something such that if it were a bird (even if it is not actually a bird), then everything would be a bird,” it seems like it should no longer be provable.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Since this may be homework, I do not want to provide the full formal proof, but I will share the informal justification. Classical first-order logic typically makes the assumption of existential import (i.e., that the domain of discourse is non-empty). In classical logic, the principle of excluded middle holds, i.e., that for any $phi$, either $phi$ or $lnotphi$ holds. Since I first encountered this kind of sentence where $P(x)$ was interpreted as "$x$ is a bird," I will use that in the following argument. Finally, recall that a material conditional $phi to psi$ is true if and only if either $phi$ is false or $psi$ is true.
By excluded middle, it is either true that everything is a bird, or that not everything is a bird. Let us consider these cases:
- If everything is a bird, then pick an arbitrary individual $x$, and note that the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird,” is true, since the consequent is true. Therefore, if everything is a bird, then there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
- If it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there must be some $x$ which is not a bird. Then consider the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird.” It is true because its antecedent, “$x$ is a bird,” is false. Therefore, if it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there is something (a non-bird, in fact) such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Since it holds in each of the exhaustive cases that there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird, we conclude that there is, in fact, something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Alternatives
Since questions about the domain came up in the comments, it seems worthwhile to consider the three preconditions to this argument: existential import (the domain is non-empty); excluded middle ($phi lor lnotphi$); and the material conditional ($(phi to psi) equiv (lnotphi lor psi)$). Each of these can be changed in a way that can affect the argument. This might not be the place to examine how each of these affects the argument, but we can at least give pointers to resources about the alternatives.
- Existential import asserts that the universe of discourse is non-empty. Free logics relax this constraint. If the universe of discourse were empty, it would seem that $exists x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ should be vacuously false.
Intuitionistic logics do not presume the excluded middle, in general. The argument above started with a claim of the form “either $phi$ or $lnotphi$.”- There are plenty of philosophical difficulties with the material conditional, especially as used to represent “if … then …” sentences in natural language. If we took the conditional to be a counterfactual, for instance, and so were considering the sentence “there is something such that if it were a bird (even if it is not actually a bird), then everything would be a bird,” it seems like it should no longer be provable.
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Since this may be homework, I do not want to provide the full formal proof, but I will share the informal justification. Classical first-order logic typically makes the assumption of existential import (i.e., that the domain of discourse is non-empty). In classical logic, the principle of excluded middle holds, i.e., that for any $phi$, either $phi$ or $lnotphi$ holds. Since I first encountered this kind of sentence where $P(x)$ was interpreted as "$x$ is a bird," I will use that in the following argument. Finally, recall that a material conditional $phi to psi$ is true if and only if either $phi$ is false or $psi$ is true.
By excluded middle, it is either true that everything is a bird, or that not everything is a bird. Let us consider these cases:
- If everything is a bird, then pick an arbitrary individual $x$, and note that the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird,” is true, since the consequent is true. Therefore, if everything is a bird, then there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
- If it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there must be some $x$ which is not a bird. Then consider the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird.” It is true because its antecedent, “$x$ is a bird,” is false. Therefore, if it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there is something (a non-bird, in fact) such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Since it holds in each of the exhaustive cases that there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird, we conclude that there is, in fact, something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Alternatives
Since questions about the domain came up in the comments, it seems worthwhile to consider the three preconditions to this argument: existential import (the domain is non-empty); excluded middle ($phi lor lnotphi$); and the material conditional ($(phi to psi) equiv (lnotphi lor psi)$). Each of these can be changed in a way that can affect the argument. This might not be the place to examine how each of these affects the argument, but we can at least give pointers to resources about the alternatives.
- Existential import asserts that the universe of discourse is non-empty. Free logics relax this constraint. If the universe of discourse were empty, it would seem that $exists x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ should be vacuously false.
Intuitionistic logics do not presume the excluded middle, in general. The argument above started with a claim of the form “either $phi$ or $lnotphi$.”- There are plenty of philosophical difficulties with the material conditional, especially as used to represent “if … then …” sentences in natural language. If we took the conditional to be a counterfactual, for instance, and so were considering the sentence “there is something such that if it were a bird (even if it is not actually a bird), then everything would be a bird,” it seems like it should no longer be provable.
$endgroup$
Since this may be homework, I do not want to provide the full formal proof, but I will share the informal justification. Classical first-order logic typically makes the assumption of existential import (i.e., that the domain of discourse is non-empty). In classical logic, the principle of excluded middle holds, i.e., that for any $phi$, either $phi$ or $lnotphi$ holds. Since I first encountered this kind of sentence where $P(x)$ was interpreted as "$x$ is a bird," I will use that in the following argument. Finally, recall that a material conditional $phi to psi$ is true if and only if either $phi$ is false or $psi$ is true.
By excluded middle, it is either true that everything is a bird, or that not everything is a bird. Let us consider these cases:
- If everything is a bird, then pick an arbitrary individual $x$, and note that the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird,” is true, since the consequent is true. Therefore, if everything is a bird, then there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
- If it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there must be some $x$ which is not a bird. Then consider the conditional “if $x$ is a bird, then everything is a bird.” It is true because its antecedent, “$x$ is a bird,” is false. Therefore, if it is not the case that everything is a bird, then there is something (a non-bird, in fact) such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Since it holds in each of the exhaustive cases that there is something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird, we conclude that there is, in fact, something such that if it is a bird, then everything is a bird.
Alternatives
Since questions about the domain came up in the comments, it seems worthwhile to consider the three preconditions to this argument: existential import (the domain is non-empty); excluded middle ($phi lor lnotphi$); and the material conditional ($(phi to psi) equiv (lnotphi lor psi)$). Each of these can be changed in a way that can affect the argument. This might not be the place to examine how each of these affects the argument, but we can at least give pointers to resources about the alternatives.
- Existential import asserts that the universe of discourse is non-empty. Free logics relax this constraint. If the universe of discourse were empty, it would seem that $exists x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ should be vacuously false.
Intuitionistic logics do not presume the excluded middle, in general. The argument above started with a claim of the form “either $phi$ or $lnotphi$.”- There are plenty of philosophical difficulties with the material conditional, especially as used to represent “if … then …” sentences in natural language. If we took the conditional to be a counterfactual, for instance, and so were considering the sentence “there is something such that if it were a bird (even if it is not actually a bird), then everything would be a bird,” it seems like it should no longer be provable.
edited Jun 5 '13 at 21:48
answered Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
Joshua TaylorJoshua Taylor
2,004830
2,004830
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
|
show 3 more comments
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
1
1
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
$begingroup$
What if your domain is empty? That is, if $exists x: Q$ is false for all statements $Q$?
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
1
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews I just meant that the semantics of classical first order logic are typically defined in terms of a semantic interpretation function $cal I$ and a variable mapping $nu$ (which maps each variable to an element of the domain) that says that a sentence $forall x. phi(x)$ is true if and only if the interpretation function and every variable mapping $nu'$ (which is the same as $nu$ for each variable excepting that it may differ on $x$) make $phi(x)$ true.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:27
1
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Regarding $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$: this sentence is a theorem of classical first-order logic. It is easy to prove by contradiction. Suppose $lnotexists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$. Then $forall x.lnot(P(x) lor lnot P(x)$, and this is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land lnotlnot P(x))$, which is equivalent to $forall x.(lnot P(x) land P(x))$, which is false if the universe of discourse is non-empty, which existential import ensures. Therefore, $exists x.(P(x) lor lnot P(x))$.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:37
1
1
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
$begingroup$
Well, non-empty discourse is what I'm talking about, so yes, if you assume some axiom that implies non-empty discourse, you are correct.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 22:24
1
1
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
$begingroup$
@ThomasAndrews Right, if you don't have existential import, then the sentence isn't necessarily true. Classical first-order logic doesn't require the assumption of “some axiom that implies non-empty discourse,” though; it's built into the inference rules. E.g., $forall x.x=x$ should be true whether the universe is empty or not. But by universal elimination we may infer $a=a$, and from that, by existential introduction, $exists x.x=x$, which implies that the domain is not empty. Free logic is a fascinating topic, and attempts to address these types of issues.
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 23:56
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Hint: The only way for $Aimplies B$ to be false is for $A$ to be true and $B$ to be false.
I don't think this is actually true unless you know your domain isn't empty. If your domain is empty, then $forall y: P(y)$ is true "vacuously," but $exists x: Q$ is not true for any $Q$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Hint: The only way for $Aimplies B$ to be false is for $A$ to be true and $B$ to be false.
I don't think this is actually true unless you know your domain isn't empty. If your domain is empty, then $forall y: P(y)$ is true "vacuously," but $exists x: Q$ is not true for any $Q$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Hint: The only way for $Aimplies B$ to be false is for $A$ to be true and $B$ to be false.
I don't think this is actually true unless you know your domain isn't empty. If your domain is empty, then $forall y: P(y)$ is true "vacuously," but $exists x: Q$ is not true for any $Q$.
$endgroup$
Hint: The only way for $Aimplies B$ to be false is for $A$ to be true and $B$ to be false.
I don't think this is actually true unless you know your domain isn't empty. If your domain is empty, then $forall y: P(y)$ is true "vacuously," but $exists x: Q$ is not true for any $Q$.
edited Jun 5 '13 at 21:09
answered Jun 5 '13 at 20:50


Thomas AndrewsThomas Andrews
130k11146297
130k11146297
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
$begingroup$
I'm probably looking at this the wrong way. But suppose P(x) means x is a person. Doesn't it say "There exists something that is a person, so everything is a person."?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 20:54
2
2
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
$begingroup$
Instead of $A Rightarrow B$, think of $lnot A lor B$.
$endgroup$
– copper.hat
Jun 5 '13 at 20:56
1
1
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
That's the problem with implication in logic. $Aimplies B$ is not a statement about "for all," it is a statement about specific instances. That can be a little confusing. If it is not true that all things are people, say, Z is my dog. Then since $P(Z)$ is false, we know that $P(Z)implies Q$ for any statement $Q$. So $exists x: P(x)implies Q$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Jun 5 '13 at 20:57
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
$begingroup$
So in my case, there exists something that isn't a person, hence the whole statement is true?
$endgroup$
– Mats
Jun 5 '13 at 21:00
4
4
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
$begingroup$
@Matts Not quite. $forall x.(P(x) to forall y.P(y))$ says that "there is an $x$ such that if $x$ is a person, then …". It does not make the assertion that "there is an $x$ such that $x$ is a person."
$endgroup$
– Joshua Taylor
Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
The examples with birds or drinkers were designed to make this simple logical truth sound paradoxical. Perhaps an example from ordinary mathematics will dispel the air of paradox. Consider a nonempty set $X$ and a function $f:Xrightarrow{0,1}$. Does the following proposition seem strange and unintuitive?
Theorem. There is an element $min X$ such that, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $xin X$.
Proof. The function $f$ has an absolute minimum. (The domain is nonempty and the range is a finite set of numbers.) Let $m$ be a point in $X$ where $f$ attains its minimum value. Clearly, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $x$.
Really, all that logical formula is saying is that the truth value ($1$ for true, $0$ for false) of the "propositional function" $P(x)$ attains its minimum.
$endgroup$
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The examples with birds or drinkers were designed to make this simple logical truth sound paradoxical. Perhaps an example from ordinary mathematics will dispel the air of paradox. Consider a nonempty set $X$ and a function $f:Xrightarrow{0,1}$. Does the following proposition seem strange and unintuitive?
Theorem. There is an element $min X$ such that, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $xin X$.
Proof. The function $f$ has an absolute minimum. (The domain is nonempty and the range is a finite set of numbers.) Let $m$ be a point in $X$ where $f$ attains its minimum value. Clearly, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $x$.
Really, all that logical formula is saying is that the truth value ($1$ for true, $0$ for false) of the "propositional function" $P(x)$ attains its minimum.
$endgroup$
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The examples with birds or drinkers were designed to make this simple logical truth sound paradoxical. Perhaps an example from ordinary mathematics will dispel the air of paradox. Consider a nonempty set $X$ and a function $f:Xrightarrow{0,1}$. Does the following proposition seem strange and unintuitive?
Theorem. There is an element $min X$ such that, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $xin X$.
Proof. The function $f$ has an absolute minimum. (The domain is nonempty and the range is a finite set of numbers.) Let $m$ be a point in $X$ where $f$ attains its minimum value. Clearly, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $x$.
Really, all that logical formula is saying is that the truth value ($1$ for true, $0$ for false) of the "propositional function" $P(x)$ attains its minimum.
$endgroup$
The examples with birds or drinkers were designed to make this simple logical truth sound paradoxical. Perhaps an example from ordinary mathematics will dispel the air of paradox. Consider a nonempty set $X$ and a function $f:Xrightarrow{0,1}$. Does the following proposition seem strange and unintuitive?
Theorem. There is an element $min X$ such that, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $xin X$.
Proof. The function $f$ has an absolute minimum. (The domain is nonempty and the range is a finite set of numbers.) Let $m$ be a point in $X$ where $f$ attains its minimum value. Clearly, if $f(m)=1$, then $f(x)=1$ for all $x$.
Really, all that logical formula is saying is that the truth value ($1$ for true, $0$ for false) of the "propositional function" $P(x)$ attains its minimum.
answered Jun 5 '13 at 21:53
user75900
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
add a comment |
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
2
2
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
The resolution of this paradox bothered me until I read this. It seemed irrelevant to declare $x$ to be "either anything, or a counterexample if there is one", since neither one is really a uniform description of a deciding element. But phrasing it like this makes it feel more acceptable since regardless of whether $f cong 1$, the description of a deciding element is the same.
$endgroup$
– Ryan Reich
Jun 5 '13 at 23:39
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
$begingroup$
In mathematics, there's no such thing as an uniform description.
$endgroup$
– justt
Jun 17 '13 at 14:35
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In classical logic the following equivalence is logically valid:
$$
exists x (varphiRightarrowpsi)Longleftrightarrow(forall xvarphiRightarrowpsi)
$$
providing that $x$ is a variable not free in $psi$. So the formula in question is logically equivalent to $forall xP(x)Rightarrowforall yP(y)$.
Looking at the poblem from a slightly different perspective. Either (i) all objects in the domain of discourse have property $P$, i.e. $forall y P(y)$ is true or (ii) there is $a$ in the domain for which $P$ fails, i.e. $neg P(a)$ is true. In (i) $P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, so $exists x(P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y))$ is true. In (ii) $P(a)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, therefore the sentence in question must be true as well.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In classical logic the following equivalence is logically valid:
$$
exists x (varphiRightarrowpsi)Longleftrightarrow(forall xvarphiRightarrowpsi)
$$
providing that $x$ is a variable not free in $psi$. So the formula in question is logically equivalent to $forall xP(x)Rightarrowforall yP(y)$.
Looking at the poblem from a slightly different perspective. Either (i) all objects in the domain of discourse have property $P$, i.e. $forall y P(y)$ is true or (ii) there is $a$ in the domain for which $P$ fails, i.e. $neg P(a)$ is true. In (i) $P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, so $exists x(P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y))$ is true. In (ii) $P(a)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, therefore the sentence in question must be true as well.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In classical logic the following equivalence is logically valid:
$$
exists x (varphiRightarrowpsi)Longleftrightarrow(forall xvarphiRightarrowpsi)
$$
providing that $x$ is a variable not free in $psi$. So the formula in question is logically equivalent to $forall xP(x)Rightarrowforall yP(y)$.
Looking at the poblem from a slightly different perspective. Either (i) all objects in the domain of discourse have property $P$, i.e. $forall y P(y)$ is true or (ii) there is $a$ in the domain for which $P$ fails, i.e. $neg P(a)$ is true. In (i) $P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, so $exists x(P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y))$ is true. In (ii) $P(a)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, therefore the sentence in question must be true as well.
$endgroup$
In classical logic the following equivalence is logically valid:
$$
exists x (varphiRightarrowpsi)Longleftrightarrow(forall xvarphiRightarrowpsi)
$$
providing that $x$ is a variable not free in $psi$. So the formula in question is logically equivalent to $forall xP(x)Rightarrowforall yP(y)$.
Looking at the poblem from a slightly different perspective. Either (i) all objects in the domain of discourse have property $P$, i.e. $forall y P(y)$ is true or (ii) there is $a$ in the domain for which $P$ fails, i.e. $neg P(a)$ is true. In (i) $P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, so $exists x(P(x)Rightarrowforall y P(y))$ is true. In (ii) $P(a)Rightarrowforall y P(y)$ must be true, therefore the sentence in question must be true as well.
answered Jun 5 '13 at 21:03
Mad HatterMad Hatter
481213
481213
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In mathematics, if not in philosophy, the domain of quantification is usually made explicit in statements. If we let the domain be some set $U$, your statement becomes
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
or equivalently
$$exists x(xin U wedge (P(x) Rightarrow forall y(yin URightarrow P(y))))$$
Then you can formally prove this statement is true iff $U$ is non-empty as sketched here:
For non-empty $U$, consider two cases:
$$forall yin U (P(y))lor negforall yin U (P(y))$$
In each case, obtain
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
For empty U, assume to the contrary that
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
and obtain a contradiction.
Full text of formal proof at http://dcproof.com/Mats.htm
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In mathematics, if not in philosophy, the domain of quantification is usually made explicit in statements. If we let the domain be some set $U$, your statement becomes
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
or equivalently
$$exists x(xin U wedge (P(x) Rightarrow forall y(yin URightarrow P(y))))$$
Then you can formally prove this statement is true iff $U$ is non-empty as sketched here:
For non-empty $U$, consider two cases:
$$forall yin U (P(y))lor negforall yin U (P(y))$$
In each case, obtain
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
For empty U, assume to the contrary that
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
and obtain a contradiction.
Full text of formal proof at http://dcproof.com/Mats.htm
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In mathematics, if not in philosophy, the domain of quantification is usually made explicit in statements. If we let the domain be some set $U$, your statement becomes
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
or equivalently
$$exists x(xin U wedge (P(x) Rightarrow forall y(yin URightarrow P(y))))$$
Then you can formally prove this statement is true iff $U$ is non-empty as sketched here:
For non-empty $U$, consider two cases:
$$forall yin U (P(y))lor negforall yin U (P(y))$$
In each case, obtain
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
For empty U, assume to the contrary that
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
and obtain a contradiction.
Full text of formal proof at http://dcproof.com/Mats.htm
$endgroup$
In mathematics, if not in philosophy, the domain of quantification is usually made explicit in statements. If we let the domain be some set $U$, your statement becomes
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
or equivalently
$$exists x(xin U wedge (P(x) Rightarrow forall y(yin URightarrow P(y))))$$
Then you can formally prove this statement is true iff $U$ is non-empty as sketched here:
For non-empty $U$, consider two cases:
$$forall yin U (P(y))lor negforall yin U (P(y))$$
In each case, obtain
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
For empty U, assume to the contrary that
$$exists xin U (P(x) Rightarrow forall yin U (P(y))$$
and obtain a contradiction.
Full text of formal proof at http://dcproof.com/Mats.htm
edited Jun 17 '13 at 19:55
answered Jun 17 '13 at 17:09


Dan ChristensenDan Christensen
8,60321833
8,60321833
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
add a comment |
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 You can use either sets or predicates to restrict the domains of quantification. For some reason, I find $xin U$ easier to visualize that $U(x)$. In mathematical proofs, you would usually use a set.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 9 '18 at 18:52
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
$begingroup$
@j4nbur53 Not a problem in this case. No axioms of set theory are used, so $in U$ is just another predicate.
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Oct 10 '18 at 3:38
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's a different approach: this can be fairly-straightforwardly proved from simple boolean algebra, starting from a tautology.$quad$
$$
((forall y)P(y)) lor (lnot (forall x) P(x)) \
((forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)lnot P(x))\
(text{anything} Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow text{anything})) \
((forall x)P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))
$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's a different approach: this can be fairly-straightforwardly proved from simple boolean algebra, starting from a tautology.$quad$
$$
((forall y)P(y)) lor (lnot (forall x) P(x)) \
((forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)lnot P(x))\
(text{anything} Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow text{anything})) \
((forall x)P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))
$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's a different approach: this can be fairly-straightforwardly proved from simple boolean algebra, starting from a tautology.$quad$
$$
((forall y)P(y)) lor (lnot (forall x) P(x)) \
((forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)lnot P(x))\
(text{anything} Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow text{anything})) \
((forall x)P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))
$$
$endgroup$
Here's a different approach: this can be fairly-straightforwardly proved from simple boolean algebra, starting from a tautology.$quad$
$$
((forall y)P(y)) lor (lnot (forall x) P(x)) \
((forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)lnot P(x))\
(text{anything} Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow text{anything})) \
((forall x)P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y)) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) lor ((exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))) \
(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y)P(y))
$$
edited Oct 9 '18 at 18:51


j4n bur53
1,4091330
1,4091330
answered Jun 5 '13 at 22:28
Joe KJoe K
1,410710
1,410710
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The location of the parentheses is crucial here. Note that $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$ is very different from $(exists x)(P(x)) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$. To see why the former statement is true, consider its negation which is
$$forall x (P(x) wedge neg forall P(x)) equiv forall x(P(x) wedge exists x neg P(x))$$
which is clearly false if your domain is nonempty. In classical logic, we restrict to nonempty domains, so your original statement will always be true.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The location of the parentheses is crucial here. Note that $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$ is very different from $(exists x)(P(x)) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$. To see why the former statement is true, consider its negation which is
$$forall x (P(x) wedge neg forall P(x)) equiv forall x(P(x) wedge exists x neg P(x))$$
which is clearly false if your domain is nonempty. In classical logic, we restrict to nonempty domains, so your original statement will always be true.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The location of the parentheses is crucial here. Note that $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$ is very different from $(exists x)(P(x)) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$. To see why the former statement is true, consider its negation which is
$$forall x (P(x) wedge neg forall P(x)) equiv forall x(P(x) wedge exists x neg P(x))$$
which is clearly false if your domain is nonempty. In classical logic, we restrict to nonempty domains, so your original statement will always be true.
$endgroup$
The location of the parentheses is crucial here. Note that $(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$ is very different from $(exists x)(P(x)) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$. To see why the former statement is true, consider its negation which is
$$forall x (P(x) wedge neg forall P(x)) equiv forall x(P(x) wedge exists x neg P(x))$$
which is clearly false if your domain is nonempty. In classical logic, we restrict to nonempty domains, so your original statement will always be true.
edited Jun 5 '13 at 21:43
answered Jun 5 '13 at 21:14


InkInk
4,46611017
4,46611017
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Translate it to english:
In any universe of things, there can always be found an instance which, if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
For any given property, you can find an instance in a set of things to make it true. (As long as that set is not the empty set, by the way; existential assertions are false for empty sets.)
If none of the things have the property, then you can choose any one of them. Call that chosen instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is vacuously true, because $P Rightarrow Q$ is true whenever $P$ is false.
If all of the things have the property, then you can also choose any of them to be the instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is then true because $P(a)$ is true, and $(forall y) P(y)$ is true.
If some things have the property but not others, then you just choose one which does not have the property to be the instance $a$. Then $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is, again, vacuously true on account of $P(a)$ being false.
But let's look at it by taking the contradiction and seeing where it leads: $neg(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, there cannot be found an instance such that if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
we can move the negative inside: $(forall x)neg(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, for every one of its elements, it is false that if a given property holds true of the element, then it holds for all other elements.
Then we can integrate the $neg$ into the formula by way of $neg (Q rightarrow P) = Q landneg P$ to arrive at: $(forall x)(P(x) landneg (forall y) P(y))$
But this asserts $P(x)$ for all $x$; i.e. that if we think of any property $P$, all things have that property! This is clearly absurd for any nonempty set; we can come up with all kinds of properties $P$ which holds only for some things in a set, or none at all.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Translate it to english:
In any universe of things, there can always be found an instance which, if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
For any given property, you can find an instance in a set of things to make it true. (As long as that set is not the empty set, by the way; existential assertions are false for empty sets.)
If none of the things have the property, then you can choose any one of them. Call that chosen instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is vacuously true, because $P Rightarrow Q$ is true whenever $P$ is false.
If all of the things have the property, then you can also choose any of them to be the instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is then true because $P(a)$ is true, and $(forall y) P(y)$ is true.
If some things have the property but not others, then you just choose one which does not have the property to be the instance $a$. Then $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is, again, vacuously true on account of $P(a)$ being false.
But let's look at it by taking the contradiction and seeing where it leads: $neg(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, there cannot be found an instance such that if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
we can move the negative inside: $(forall x)neg(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, for every one of its elements, it is false that if a given property holds true of the element, then it holds for all other elements.
Then we can integrate the $neg$ into the formula by way of $neg (Q rightarrow P) = Q landneg P$ to arrive at: $(forall x)(P(x) landneg (forall y) P(y))$
But this asserts $P(x)$ for all $x$; i.e. that if we think of any property $P$, all things have that property! This is clearly absurd for any nonempty set; we can come up with all kinds of properties $P$ which holds only for some things in a set, or none at all.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Translate it to english:
In any universe of things, there can always be found an instance which, if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
For any given property, you can find an instance in a set of things to make it true. (As long as that set is not the empty set, by the way; existential assertions are false for empty sets.)
If none of the things have the property, then you can choose any one of them. Call that chosen instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is vacuously true, because $P Rightarrow Q$ is true whenever $P$ is false.
If all of the things have the property, then you can also choose any of them to be the instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is then true because $P(a)$ is true, and $(forall y) P(y)$ is true.
If some things have the property but not others, then you just choose one which does not have the property to be the instance $a$. Then $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is, again, vacuously true on account of $P(a)$ being false.
But let's look at it by taking the contradiction and seeing where it leads: $neg(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, there cannot be found an instance such that if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
we can move the negative inside: $(forall x)neg(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, for every one of its elements, it is false that if a given property holds true of the element, then it holds for all other elements.
Then we can integrate the $neg$ into the formula by way of $neg (Q rightarrow P) = Q landneg P$ to arrive at: $(forall x)(P(x) landneg (forall y) P(y))$
But this asserts $P(x)$ for all $x$; i.e. that if we think of any property $P$, all things have that property! This is clearly absurd for any nonempty set; we can come up with all kinds of properties $P$ which holds only for some things in a set, or none at all.
$endgroup$
Translate it to english:
In any universe of things, there can always be found an instance which, if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
For any given property, you can find an instance in a set of things to make it true. (As long as that set is not the empty set, by the way; existential assertions are false for empty sets.)
If none of the things have the property, then you can choose any one of them. Call that chosen instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is vacuously true, because $P Rightarrow Q$ is true whenever $P$ is false.
If all of the things have the property, then you can also choose any of them to be the instance $a$. $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is then true because $P(a)$ is true, and $(forall y) P(y)$ is true.
If some things have the property but not others, then you just choose one which does not have the property to be the instance $a$. Then $P(a) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y)$ is, again, vacuously true on account of $P(a)$ being false.
But let's look at it by taking the contradiction and seeing where it leads: $neg(exists x)(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, there cannot be found an instance such that if it has some property, then all other things have that property.
we can move the negative inside: $(forall x)neg(P(x) Rightarrow (forall y) P(y))$
In any universe of things, for every one of its elements, it is false that if a given property holds true of the element, then it holds for all other elements.
Then we can integrate the $neg$ into the formula by way of $neg (Q rightarrow P) = Q landneg P$ to arrive at: $(forall x)(P(x) landneg (forall y) P(y))$
But this asserts $P(x)$ for all $x$; i.e. that if we think of any property $P$, all things have that property! This is clearly absurd for any nonempty set; we can come up with all kinds of properties $P$ which holds only for some things in a set, or none at all.
answered Jun 5 '13 at 21:55
KazKaz
6,24311328
6,24311328
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To add a proof in Fitch style, natural deduction:
2 | |__________ ~Ex(Px -> VyPy) New Subproof for ~ Introduction
3 | | |________ Pa New Subproof for -> Introduction
4 | | | |_____b variable for Universal Introduction
5 | | | | |____ ~Pb New Subproof for ~ Introduction
6 | | | | | |__ Pb New Subproof for -> Introduction
7 | | | | | | _|_ 5,6 _|_ Introduction
8 | | | | | | VyPy 7 _|_ Elimination
. | | | | | <-------------------- end subpproof
9 | | | | | Pb -> VyPy 6-8 -> Introduction
10 | | | | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 9 Existentional Introduction
11 | | | | | _|_ 2,10 _|_ Introduction
.. | | | | <---------------------- end subpproof
12 | | | | ~~Pb 5-11 ~ Introduction
13 | | | | Pb 12 ~~ Elimination
.. | | | <------------------------ end subpproof
14 | | | VyPy 4-13 Universal Introduction
.. | | <-------------------------- end subpproof
15 | | Pa -> VyPy 3-14 -> Introduction
16 | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 15 Existentional Introduction
17 | | _|_ 2,16 _|_ Introduction
.. | <---------------------------- end subpproof
18 | ~~Ex(Px -> VyPy) 2-17 ~ Introduction
19 | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 18 ~~ Elimination
This is the shortest I managed, I don't think a shorter proof using the standard introduction and elimination rules exist
For explanation I compare this "paradox" with:
If the last person has left the room, all people have left the room.
Therefore
There is a person if he has left the room, all people have left the room.
The first statement is a truism , so how can the last statement not be one?
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To add a proof in Fitch style, natural deduction:
2 | |__________ ~Ex(Px -> VyPy) New Subproof for ~ Introduction
3 | | |________ Pa New Subproof for -> Introduction
4 | | | |_____b variable for Universal Introduction
5 | | | | |____ ~Pb New Subproof for ~ Introduction
6 | | | | | |__ Pb New Subproof for -> Introduction
7 | | | | | | _|_ 5,6 _|_ Introduction
8 | | | | | | VyPy 7 _|_ Elimination
. | | | | | <-------------------- end subpproof
9 | | | | | Pb -> VyPy 6-8 -> Introduction
10 | | | | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 9 Existentional Introduction
11 | | | | | _|_ 2,10 _|_ Introduction
.. | | | | <---------------------- end subpproof
12 | | | | ~~Pb 5-11 ~ Introduction
13 | | | | Pb 12 ~~ Elimination
.. | | | <------------------------ end subpproof
14 | | | VyPy 4-13 Universal Introduction
.. | | <-------------------------- end subpproof
15 | | Pa -> VyPy 3-14 -> Introduction
16 | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 15 Existentional Introduction
17 | | _|_ 2,16 _|_ Introduction
.. | <---------------------------- end subpproof
18 | ~~Ex(Px -> VyPy) 2-17 ~ Introduction
19 | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 18 ~~ Elimination
This is the shortest I managed, I don't think a shorter proof using the standard introduction and elimination rules exist
For explanation I compare this "paradox" with:
If the last person has left the room, all people have left the room.
Therefore
There is a person if he has left the room, all people have left the room.
The first statement is a truism , so how can the last statement not be one?
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
To add a proof in Fitch style, natural deduction:
2 | |__________ ~Ex(Px -> VyPy) New Subproof for ~ Introduction
3 | | |________ Pa New Subproof for -> Introduction
4 | | | |_____b variable for Universal Introduction
5 | | | | |____ ~Pb New Subproof for ~ Introduction
6 | | | | | |__ Pb New Subproof for -> Introduction
7 | | | | | | _|_ 5,6 _|_ Introduction
8 | | | | | | VyPy 7 _|_ Elimination
. | | | | | <-------------------- end subpproof
9 | | | | | Pb -> VyPy 6-8 -> Introduction
10 | | | | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 9 Existentional Introduction
11 | | | | | _|_ 2,10 _|_ Introduction
.. | | | | <---------------------- end subpproof
12 | | | | ~~Pb 5-11 ~ Introduction
13 | | | | Pb 12 ~~ Elimination
.. | | | <------------------------ end subpproof
14 | | | VyPy 4-13 Universal Introduction
.. | | <-------------------------- end subpproof
15 | | Pa -> VyPy 3-14 -> Introduction
16 | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 15 Existentional Introduction
17 | | _|_ 2,16 _|_ Introduction
.. | <---------------------------- end subpproof
18 | ~~Ex(Px -> VyPy) 2-17 ~ Introduction
19 | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 18 ~~ Elimination
This is the shortest I managed, I don't think a shorter proof using the standard introduction and elimination rules exist
For explanation I compare this "paradox" with:
If the last person has left the room, all people have left the room.
Therefore
There is a person if he has left the room, all people have left the room.
The first statement is a truism , so how can the last statement not be one?
$endgroup$
To add a proof in Fitch style, natural deduction:
2 | |__________ ~Ex(Px -> VyPy) New Subproof for ~ Introduction
3 | | |________ Pa New Subproof for -> Introduction
4 | | | |_____b variable for Universal Introduction
5 | | | | |____ ~Pb New Subproof for ~ Introduction
6 | | | | | |__ Pb New Subproof for -> Introduction
7 | | | | | | _|_ 5,6 _|_ Introduction
8 | | | | | | VyPy 7 _|_ Elimination
. | | | | | <-------------------- end subpproof
9 | | | | | Pb -> VyPy 6-8 -> Introduction
10 | | | | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 9 Existentional Introduction
11 | | | | | _|_ 2,10 _|_ Introduction
.. | | | | <---------------------- end subpproof
12 | | | | ~~Pb 5-11 ~ Introduction
13 | | | | Pb 12 ~~ Elimination
.. | | | <------------------------ end subpproof
14 | | | VyPy 4-13 Universal Introduction
.. | | <-------------------------- end subpproof
15 | | Pa -> VyPy 3-14 -> Introduction
16 | | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 15 Existentional Introduction
17 | | _|_ 2,16 _|_ Introduction
.. | <---------------------------- end subpproof
18 | ~~Ex(Px -> VyPy) 2-17 ~ Introduction
19 | Ex(Px -> VyPy) 18 ~~ Elimination
This is the shortest I managed, I don't think a shorter proof using the standard introduction and elimination rules exist
For explanation I compare this "paradox" with:
If the last person has left the room, all people have left the room.
Therefore
There is a person if he has left the room, all people have left the room.
The first statement is a truism , so how can the last statement not be one?
answered May 24 '14 at 12:16
WillemienWillemien
3,49531859
3,49531859
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$tag 1 exists x ; [P(x) Rightarrow forall y , P(y)]$
Claim: (1) is a tautology, since it leads to an equivalence chain that ends in a well-known tautology:
$tag 2 exists x ; [ neg P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)]$
$tag 3 exists x ; [ neg P(x)] , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 4 neg , forall x , P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 5 neg , [forall z , P(z)] , text{ or } , [forall z , P(z)]$
The equivalence chain ends with a tautology, so (1) must also be one.
We can go from (2) to (3) since the existential qualifier distributes over disjunction and $( exists x) (forall y) , P(y) equiv forall y , P(y) $.
In (5) the $[;]$ brackets were put around identical expressions. It was not necessary to change both $x$ and $y$ to $z$ - they both were 'quantified away' and can be viewed as just logical placeholders.
Finally, this paradox can be viewed as a contortion of counterexample logic. The only useful tautology is (3); you can replace the $text{or-disjunction}$ with $text{XOR}$ (exclusive or).
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$tag 1 exists x ; [P(x) Rightarrow forall y , P(y)]$
Claim: (1) is a tautology, since it leads to an equivalence chain that ends in a well-known tautology:
$tag 2 exists x ; [ neg P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)]$
$tag 3 exists x ; [ neg P(x)] , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 4 neg , forall x , P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 5 neg , [forall z , P(z)] , text{ or } , [forall z , P(z)]$
The equivalence chain ends with a tautology, so (1) must also be one.
We can go from (2) to (3) since the existential qualifier distributes over disjunction and $( exists x) (forall y) , P(y) equiv forall y , P(y) $.
In (5) the $[;]$ brackets were put around identical expressions. It was not necessary to change both $x$ and $y$ to $z$ - they both were 'quantified away' and can be viewed as just logical placeholders.
Finally, this paradox can be viewed as a contortion of counterexample logic. The only useful tautology is (3); you can replace the $text{or-disjunction}$ with $text{XOR}$ (exclusive or).
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$tag 1 exists x ; [P(x) Rightarrow forall y , P(y)]$
Claim: (1) is a tautology, since it leads to an equivalence chain that ends in a well-known tautology:
$tag 2 exists x ; [ neg P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)]$
$tag 3 exists x ; [ neg P(x)] , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 4 neg , forall x , P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 5 neg , [forall z , P(z)] , text{ or } , [forall z , P(z)]$
The equivalence chain ends with a tautology, so (1) must also be one.
We can go from (2) to (3) since the existential qualifier distributes over disjunction and $( exists x) (forall y) , P(y) equiv forall y , P(y) $.
In (5) the $[;]$ brackets were put around identical expressions. It was not necessary to change both $x$ and $y$ to $z$ - they both were 'quantified away' and can be viewed as just logical placeholders.
Finally, this paradox can be viewed as a contortion of counterexample logic. The only useful tautology is (3); you can replace the $text{or-disjunction}$ with $text{XOR}$ (exclusive or).
$endgroup$
$tag 1 exists x ; [P(x) Rightarrow forall y , P(y)]$
Claim: (1) is a tautology, since it leads to an equivalence chain that ends in a well-known tautology:
$tag 2 exists x ; [ neg P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)]$
$tag 3 exists x ; [ neg P(x)] , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 4 neg , forall x , P(x) , text{ or } , forall y , P(y)$
$tag 5 neg , [forall z , P(z)] , text{ or } , [forall z , P(z)]$
The equivalence chain ends with a tautology, so (1) must also be one.
We can go from (2) to (3) since the existential qualifier distributes over disjunction and $( exists x) (forall y) , P(y) equiv forall y , P(y) $.
In (5) the $[;]$ brackets were put around identical expressions. It was not necessary to change both $x$ and $y$ to $z$ - they both were 'quantified away' and can be viewed as just logical placeholders.
Finally, this paradox can be viewed as a contortion of counterexample logic. The only useful tautology is (3); you can replace the $text{or-disjunction}$ with $text{XOR}$ (exclusive or).
edited Sep 10 '17 at 3:31
answered Sep 9 '17 at 2:14
CopyPasteItCopyPasteIt
4,1481628
4,1481628
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here is a sequent calculus style proof:
------------ (Id)
P(y) |- P(y)
--------------------- (Weak Right)
P(y) |- P(y), ∀yP(y)
--------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(y), P(y)⇒∀yP(y)
------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- P(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
--------------------------- (∀ Right)
|- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------- (Weak Left)
P(z) |- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
-------------------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(z)⇒∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y)), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (Contr Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
It uses a multi-consequent sequent calculus, so possibly
cannot be reduced to intuitionistic logic. Also the
contraction structural rule shows that a substructural
logic would possibly not do. These speculations could
possibly substantiated by some non-classical logic model
theoretic considerations.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here is a sequent calculus style proof:
------------ (Id)
P(y) |- P(y)
--------------------- (Weak Right)
P(y) |- P(y), ∀yP(y)
--------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(y), P(y)⇒∀yP(y)
------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- P(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
--------------------------- (∀ Right)
|- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------- (Weak Left)
P(z) |- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
-------------------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(z)⇒∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y)), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (Contr Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
It uses a multi-consequent sequent calculus, so possibly
cannot be reduced to intuitionistic logic. Also the
contraction structural rule shows that a substructural
logic would possibly not do. These speculations could
possibly substantiated by some non-classical logic model
theoretic considerations.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here is a sequent calculus style proof:
------------ (Id)
P(y) |- P(y)
--------------------- (Weak Right)
P(y) |- P(y), ∀yP(y)
--------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(y), P(y)⇒∀yP(y)
------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- P(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
--------------------------- (∀ Right)
|- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------- (Weak Left)
P(z) |- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
-------------------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(z)⇒∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y)), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (Contr Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
It uses a multi-consequent sequent calculus, so possibly
cannot be reduced to intuitionistic logic. Also the
contraction structural rule shows that a substructural
logic would possibly not do. These speculations could
possibly substantiated by some non-classical logic model
theoretic considerations.
$endgroup$
Here is a sequent calculus style proof:
------------ (Id)
P(y) |- P(y)
--------------------- (Weak Right)
P(y) |- P(y), ∀yP(y)
--------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(y), P(y)⇒∀yP(y)
------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- P(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
--------------------------- (∀ Right)
|- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------- (Weak Left)
P(z) |- ∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
-------------------------------- (⇒ Right)
|- P(z)⇒∀yP(y), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (∃ Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y)), ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
------------------------------------- (Contr Right)
|- ∃x(P(x)⇒∀yP(y))
It uses a multi-consequent sequent calculus, so possibly
cannot be reduced to intuitionistic logic. Also the
contraction structural rule shows that a substructural
logic would possibly not do. These speculations could
possibly substantiated by some non-classical logic model
theoretic considerations.
answered Oct 12 '18 at 8:41


j4n bur53j4n bur53
1,4091330
1,4091330
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f412387%2fwhy-is-this-true-exists-xpx-rightarrow-forall-y-py%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
4
$begingroup$
Smullyan calls this the "drinker's paradox": there exists a person $p$ such that if $p$ drinks, then everyone drinks.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Jun 5 '13 at 21:14
1
$begingroup$
See my math blog posting, "The Drinker's Paradox" (dated June 3, 2014) at dcproof.wordpress.com
$endgroup$
– Dan Christensen
Jun 3 '14 at 20:56