Intuition for the Stone-Čech compactification via ultrafilters












3












$begingroup$


Definitions used:



Given some set $X$, denote by $beta X$ the set of ultrafilters on $X$. We can view $X$ as a subset of $beta X$ by identifying each point $x in X$ with the principal ultrafilter associated to $x$. Further, the collection of all sets of the form $widehat{A} = { mathcal{U} in beta X | A in mathcal{U} }$ supplies us with a basis for a topology on $beta X$.



If we view $X$ as a discrete space and equip $beta X$ with the topology generated by the aforementioned basis, then $beta X$ is termed the Stone-Čech compactification of $X$. The space $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff; the proofs of both of these facts are routine.





My question:



Purely formally, I feel that I understand all of the above, in the sense that I can solve a problem of the kind "given the set $X$, define the set $beta X$ as above; verify that what we claim to be a basis is indeed a basis, and show that under the topology generated by this basis $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff" painlessly.



My issue is that I have no sense of why we might expect $beta X$ to be compact Hausdorff in the first place. Is this something that could be anticipated, or is it just a happy accident that we find when asking ourselves (quite reasonably) whether or not $beta X$ has these properties?





My intuition:



In general, I think of compactifications as "adding points at infinity" so that anything that wants to "escape to infinity" gets "captured". This is pretty vague, but works reasonably well for (e.g.) the Alexandroff compactification. The Alexandroff compactification of $mathbb{R}$ is just $S^1$, so that anything that can run away to infinity in $mathbb{R}$ ends up "looping back around" in $S^1$.



I have less intuition for (ultra)filters, and tend to think of filters as being prescriptions for saying when certain subsets of a set $X$ are "large enough", and of an ultrafilter extending a given filter as being a (not, in general, unique) way of consistently extending that prescription to apply to all subsets of $X$. This basically came from the answers of Henning Makholm and Asaf Karagila to this math.SE question.



Unfortunately, I'm struggling to use this understanding of ultrafilters and compactifications to see why we would suspect that $beta X$ is compact Hausdorff before outright proving it.



(I apologise for such a vague question being so long: given how what I ask is in some senses nebulous and non-concrete, I wanted to be completely explicit about both the definitions I use and the intuition that I already have).










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$

















    3












    $begingroup$


    Definitions used:



    Given some set $X$, denote by $beta X$ the set of ultrafilters on $X$. We can view $X$ as a subset of $beta X$ by identifying each point $x in X$ with the principal ultrafilter associated to $x$. Further, the collection of all sets of the form $widehat{A} = { mathcal{U} in beta X | A in mathcal{U} }$ supplies us with a basis for a topology on $beta X$.



    If we view $X$ as a discrete space and equip $beta X$ with the topology generated by the aforementioned basis, then $beta X$ is termed the Stone-Čech compactification of $X$. The space $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff; the proofs of both of these facts are routine.





    My question:



    Purely formally, I feel that I understand all of the above, in the sense that I can solve a problem of the kind "given the set $X$, define the set $beta X$ as above; verify that what we claim to be a basis is indeed a basis, and show that under the topology generated by this basis $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff" painlessly.



    My issue is that I have no sense of why we might expect $beta X$ to be compact Hausdorff in the first place. Is this something that could be anticipated, or is it just a happy accident that we find when asking ourselves (quite reasonably) whether or not $beta X$ has these properties?





    My intuition:



    In general, I think of compactifications as "adding points at infinity" so that anything that wants to "escape to infinity" gets "captured". This is pretty vague, but works reasonably well for (e.g.) the Alexandroff compactification. The Alexandroff compactification of $mathbb{R}$ is just $S^1$, so that anything that can run away to infinity in $mathbb{R}$ ends up "looping back around" in $S^1$.



    I have less intuition for (ultra)filters, and tend to think of filters as being prescriptions for saying when certain subsets of a set $X$ are "large enough", and of an ultrafilter extending a given filter as being a (not, in general, unique) way of consistently extending that prescription to apply to all subsets of $X$. This basically came from the answers of Henning Makholm and Asaf Karagila to this math.SE question.



    Unfortunately, I'm struggling to use this understanding of ultrafilters and compactifications to see why we would suspect that $beta X$ is compact Hausdorff before outright proving it.



    (I apologise for such a vague question being so long: given how what I ask is in some senses nebulous and non-concrete, I wanted to be completely explicit about both the definitions I use and the intuition that I already have).










    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$















      3












      3








      3


      1



      $begingroup$


      Definitions used:



      Given some set $X$, denote by $beta X$ the set of ultrafilters on $X$. We can view $X$ as a subset of $beta X$ by identifying each point $x in X$ with the principal ultrafilter associated to $x$. Further, the collection of all sets of the form $widehat{A} = { mathcal{U} in beta X | A in mathcal{U} }$ supplies us with a basis for a topology on $beta X$.



      If we view $X$ as a discrete space and equip $beta X$ with the topology generated by the aforementioned basis, then $beta X$ is termed the Stone-Čech compactification of $X$. The space $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff; the proofs of both of these facts are routine.





      My question:



      Purely formally, I feel that I understand all of the above, in the sense that I can solve a problem of the kind "given the set $X$, define the set $beta X$ as above; verify that what we claim to be a basis is indeed a basis, and show that under the topology generated by this basis $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff" painlessly.



      My issue is that I have no sense of why we might expect $beta X$ to be compact Hausdorff in the first place. Is this something that could be anticipated, or is it just a happy accident that we find when asking ourselves (quite reasonably) whether or not $beta X$ has these properties?





      My intuition:



      In general, I think of compactifications as "adding points at infinity" so that anything that wants to "escape to infinity" gets "captured". This is pretty vague, but works reasonably well for (e.g.) the Alexandroff compactification. The Alexandroff compactification of $mathbb{R}$ is just $S^1$, so that anything that can run away to infinity in $mathbb{R}$ ends up "looping back around" in $S^1$.



      I have less intuition for (ultra)filters, and tend to think of filters as being prescriptions for saying when certain subsets of a set $X$ are "large enough", and of an ultrafilter extending a given filter as being a (not, in general, unique) way of consistently extending that prescription to apply to all subsets of $X$. This basically came from the answers of Henning Makholm and Asaf Karagila to this math.SE question.



      Unfortunately, I'm struggling to use this understanding of ultrafilters and compactifications to see why we would suspect that $beta X$ is compact Hausdorff before outright proving it.



      (I apologise for such a vague question being so long: given how what I ask is in some senses nebulous and non-concrete, I wanted to be completely explicit about both the definitions I use and the intuition that I already have).










      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      Definitions used:



      Given some set $X$, denote by $beta X$ the set of ultrafilters on $X$. We can view $X$ as a subset of $beta X$ by identifying each point $x in X$ with the principal ultrafilter associated to $x$. Further, the collection of all sets of the form $widehat{A} = { mathcal{U} in beta X | A in mathcal{U} }$ supplies us with a basis for a topology on $beta X$.



      If we view $X$ as a discrete space and equip $beta X$ with the topology generated by the aforementioned basis, then $beta X$ is termed the Stone-Čech compactification of $X$. The space $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff; the proofs of both of these facts are routine.





      My question:



      Purely formally, I feel that I understand all of the above, in the sense that I can solve a problem of the kind "given the set $X$, define the set $beta X$ as above; verify that what we claim to be a basis is indeed a basis, and show that under the topology generated by this basis $beta X$ is both compact and Hausdorff" painlessly.



      My issue is that I have no sense of why we might expect $beta X$ to be compact Hausdorff in the first place. Is this something that could be anticipated, or is it just a happy accident that we find when asking ourselves (quite reasonably) whether or not $beta X$ has these properties?





      My intuition:



      In general, I think of compactifications as "adding points at infinity" so that anything that wants to "escape to infinity" gets "captured". This is pretty vague, but works reasonably well for (e.g.) the Alexandroff compactification. The Alexandroff compactification of $mathbb{R}$ is just $S^1$, so that anything that can run away to infinity in $mathbb{R}$ ends up "looping back around" in $S^1$.



      I have less intuition for (ultra)filters, and tend to think of filters as being prescriptions for saying when certain subsets of a set $X$ are "large enough", and of an ultrafilter extending a given filter as being a (not, in general, unique) way of consistently extending that prescription to apply to all subsets of $X$. This basically came from the answers of Henning Makholm and Asaf Karagila to this math.SE question.



      Unfortunately, I'm struggling to use this understanding of ultrafilters and compactifications to see why we would suspect that $beta X$ is compact Hausdorff before outright proving it.



      (I apologise for such a vague question being so long: given how what I ask is in some senses nebulous and non-concrete, I wanted to be completely explicit about both the definitions I use and the intuition that I already have).







      general-topology intuition filters compactification






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Jan 26 at 13:36









      JackJack

      1814




      1814






















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          2












          $begingroup$

          Since you already know about the Alexandroff one-point compactification, let me begin by saying that the Stone-Cech compactification is at the other extreme, adding as many points at infinity as possible. To see what that could mean, let's consider some other compactifications of $mathbb R$, starting with the most familiar, the extended real line, obtained by adjoining the two points $+infty$ and $-infty$ at the two ends of the line. Compared with the Alexandroff compactification, we're now distinguishing two different ways of "going to infinity". Some sequences that converged to $infty$ in the Alexandroff compactification fail to converge in the extended real line because part of the sequence goes to the left and part to the right (e.g., $(-1)^nn$).



          This idea can be extended, to produce "bigger" compactifications. If you visualize $mathbb R$ as embedded in the plane as the graph of the sine function and then take its closure in the extended plane $(mathbb Rcup{+infty,-infty})^2$, you get a compactification with a whole line segment at $+infty$ (and another at $-infty$). Similarly, embedding $mathbb R$ in $3$-dimensional space as a helix, by $xmapsto (x,cos x,sin x)$, we get a compactification with circles at the ends. Proceeding analogously with all bounded continuous functions $mathbb Rtomathbb R$ (in place of $cos$ and $sin$), in a very high-dimensional space (in fact, $2^{aleph_0}$ dimensions), you get one of the standard constructions of the Stone-Cech compactification of $mathbb R$. Roughly speaking, it separates, into different points at infinity, all of the possible "ways to go to $infty$" in $mathbb R$.



          The analogous story works for discrete spaces $X$ in place of $mathbb R$ (except that I don't need to say "continuous" because all functions on a discrete space are continuous). A point in the Stone-Cech remainder of a discrete space $X$ should be thought of as a "way to go to $infty$" in $X$. But how can such "ways" be described?



          Well, in any compactification, each point $p$ at infinity is in the closure of the original space $X$, and so we can describe its location relative to $X$ by the trace on $X$ of its neighborhood filter, i.e. by $mathcal F={Ucap X: pintext{interior}(U)}$ (where $U$ refers to subsets of the compactification). Note that $mathcal F$ can't contain any finite subsets of $X$, because such subsets are closed in the compactification (as in any $T_1$ space) and thus disjoint from suitable neighborhoods of any point $p$ at infinity.



          For the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space $X$, this filter $mathcal F$ must have one additional property, namely that we cannot have two disjoint subsets $A,B$ of $X$ both meeting all the sets in $mathcal F$. The reason is that then "going to infinity" in $A$ and in $B$ would be two different ways to go to infinity, both leading to the same point $p$.



          This additional property of the filter $mathcal F$ is equivalent to saying that $mathcal F$ is an ultrafilter. So this is how ultrafilters enter the picture of Stone-Cech compactifications of discrete spaces.



          One then ordinarily continues by saying that, (1) since the filter $mathcal F$ associated with any $p$ at infinity is an ultrafilter, and different $p$'s must correspond to different ultrafilters (in order for the compactification to be Hausdorff), we might as well identify the points $p$ with the ultrafilters $mathcal F$, and (2) for the sake of uniformity, we might as well identify the principal ultrafilters (which haven't been used yet) with the points of $X$. With these conventions, one can prove (using compactness) that every ultrafilter on $X$ gets identified with a point in the Stone-Cech compactification of $X$. So the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space can be identified with the set of ultrafilters on $X$. Finally, one should verify that the topology is necessarily the one you described.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$





















            2












            $begingroup$

            If we have a space $S$ then one can show (it's classical) that $S$ is compact iff every ultrafilter on $S$ has a limit in $S$.



            So for an infinite discrete space (which has no ultrafilter limits, except for the fixed ultrafilters) we need to add a point to be a limit for each ultrafilter, and $beta(S)$ will be the maximal compactification, so we add a different point for each ultrafilter (the one-point compactification adds just one point for all of them).






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













              Your Answer





              StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
              return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
              StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
              StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
              });
              });
              }, "mathjax-editing");

              StackExchange.ready(function() {
              var channelOptions = {
              tags: "".split(" "),
              id: "69"
              };
              initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

              StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
              // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
              if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
              StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
              createEditor();
              });
              }
              else {
              createEditor();
              }
              });

              function createEditor() {
              StackExchange.prepareEditor({
              heartbeatType: 'answer',
              autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
              convertImagesToLinks: true,
              noModals: true,
              showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
              reputationToPostImages: 10,
              bindNavPrevention: true,
              postfix: "",
              imageUploader: {
              brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
              contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
              allowUrls: true
              },
              noCode: true, onDemand: true,
              discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
              ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
              });


              }
              });














              draft saved

              draft discarded


















              StackExchange.ready(
              function () {
              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3088257%2fintuition-for-the-stone-%25c4%258cech-compactification-via-ultrafilters%23new-answer', 'question_page');
              }
              );

              Post as a guest















              Required, but never shown

























              2 Answers
              2






              active

              oldest

              votes








              2 Answers
              2






              active

              oldest

              votes









              active

              oldest

              votes






              active

              oldest

              votes









              2












              $begingroup$

              Since you already know about the Alexandroff one-point compactification, let me begin by saying that the Stone-Cech compactification is at the other extreme, adding as many points at infinity as possible. To see what that could mean, let's consider some other compactifications of $mathbb R$, starting with the most familiar, the extended real line, obtained by adjoining the two points $+infty$ and $-infty$ at the two ends of the line. Compared with the Alexandroff compactification, we're now distinguishing two different ways of "going to infinity". Some sequences that converged to $infty$ in the Alexandroff compactification fail to converge in the extended real line because part of the sequence goes to the left and part to the right (e.g., $(-1)^nn$).



              This idea can be extended, to produce "bigger" compactifications. If you visualize $mathbb R$ as embedded in the plane as the graph of the sine function and then take its closure in the extended plane $(mathbb Rcup{+infty,-infty})^2$, you get a compactification with a whole line segment at $+infty$ (and another at $-infty$). Similarly, embedding $mathbb R$ in $3$-dimensional space as a helix, by $xmapsto (x,cos x,sin x)$, we get a compactification with circles at the ends. Proceeding analogously with all bounded continuous functions $mathbb Rtomathbb R$ (in place of $cos$ and $sin$), in a very high-dimensional space (in fact, $2^{aleph_0}$ dimensions), you get one of the standard constructions of the Stone-Cech compactification of $mathbb R$. Roughly speaking, it separates, into different points at infinity, all of the possible "ways to go to $infty$" in $mathbb R$.



              The analogous story works for discrete spaces $X$ in place of $mathbb R$ (except that I don't need to say "continuous" because all functions on a discrete space are continuous). A point in the Stone-Cech remainder of a discrete space $X$ should be thought of as a "way to go to $infty$" in $X$. But how can such "ways" be described?



              Well, in any compactification, each point $p$ at infinity is in the closure of the original space $X$, and so we can describe its location relative to $X$ by the trace on $X$ of its neighborhood filter, i.e. by $mathcal F={Ucap X: pintext{interior}(U)}$ (where $U$ refers to subsets of the compactification). Note that $mathcal F$ can't contain any finite subsets of $X$, because such subsets are closed in the compactification (as in any $T_1$ space) and thus disjoint from suitable neighborhoods of any point $p$ at infinity.



              For the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space $X$, this filter $mathcal F$ must have one additional property, namely that we cannot have two disjoint subsets $A,B$ of $X$ both meeting all the sets in $mathcal F$. The reason is that then "going to infinity" in $A$ and in $B$ would be two different ways to go to infinity, both leading to the same point $p$.



              This additional property of the filter $mathcal F$ is equivalent to saying that $mathcal F$ is an ultrafilter. So this is how ultrafilters enter the picture of Stone-Cech compactifications of discrete spaces.



              One then ordinarily continues by saying that, (1) since the filter $mathcal F$ associated with any $p$ at infinity is an ultrafilter, and different $p$'s must correspond to different ultrafilters (in order for the compactification to be Hausdorff), we might as well identify the points $p$ with the ultrafilters $mathcal F$, and (2) for the sake of uniformity, we might as well identify the principal ultrafilters (which haven't been used yet) with the points of $X$. With these conventions, one can prove (using compactness) that every ultrafilter on $X$ gets identified with a point in the Stone-Cech compactification of $X$. So the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space can be identified with the set of ultrafilters on $X$. Finally, one should verify that the topology is necessarily the one you described.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                2












                $begingroup$

                Since you already know about the Alexandroff one-point compactification, let me begin by saying that the Stone-Cech compactification is at the other extreme, adding as many points at infinity as possible. To see what that could mean, let's consider some other compactifications of $mathbb R$, starting with the most familiar, the extended real line, obtained by adjoining the two points $+infty$ and $-infty$ at the two ends of the line. Compared with the Alexandroff compactification, we're now distinguishing two different ways of "going to infinity". Some sequences that converged to $infty$ in the Alexandroff compactification fail to converge in the extended real line because part of the sequence goes to the left and part to the right (e.g., $(-1)^nn$).



                This idea can be extended, to produce "bigger" compactifications. If you visualize $mathbb R$ as embedded in the plane as the graph of the sine function and then take its closure in the extended plane $(mathbb Rcup{+infty,-infty})^2$, you get a compactification with a whole line segment at $+infty$ (and another at $-infty$). Similarly, embedding $mathbb R$ in $3$-dimensional space as a helix, by $xmapsto (x,cos x,sin x)$, we get a compactification with circles at the ends. Proceeding analogously with all bounded continuous functions $mathbb Rtomathbb R$ (in place of $cos$ and $sin$), in a very high-dimensional space (in fact, $2^{aleph_0}$ dimensions), you get one of the standard constructions of the Stone-Cech compactification of $mathbb R$. Roughly speaking, it separates, into different points at infinity, all of the possible "ways to go to $infty$" in $mathbb R$.



                The analogous story works for discrete spaces $X$ in place of $mathbb R$ (except that I don't need to say "continuous" because all functions on a discrete space are continuous). A point in the Stone-Cech remainder of a discrete space $X$ should be thought of as a "way to go to $infty$" in $X$. But how can such "ways" be described?



                Well, in any compactification, each point $p$ at infinity is in the closure of the original space $X$, and so we can describe its location relative to $X$ by the trace on $X$ of its neighborhood filter, i.e. by $mathcal F={Ucap X: pintext{interior}(U)}$ (where $U$ refers to subsets of the compactification). Note that $mathcal F$ can't contain any finite subsets of $X$, because such subsets are closed in the compactification (as in any $T_1$ space) and thus disjoint from suitable neighborhoods of any point $p$ at infinity.



                For the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space $X$, this filter $mathcal F$ must have one additional property, namely that we cannot have two disjoint subsets $A,B$ of $X$ both meeting all the sets in $mathcal F$. The reason is that then "going to infinity" in $A$ and in $B$ would be two different ways to go to infinity, both leading to the same point $p$.



                This additional property of the filter $mathcal F$ is equivalent to saying that $mathcal F$ is an ultrafilter. So this is how ultrafilters enter the picture of Stone-Cech compactifications of discrete spaces.



                One then ordinarily continues by saying that, (1) since the filter $mathcal F$ associated with any $p$ at infinity is an ultrafilter, and different $p$'s must correspond to different ultrafilters (in order for the compactification to be Hausdorff), we might as well identify the points $p$ with the ultrafilters $mathcal F$, and (2) for the sake of uniformity, we might as well identify the principal ultrafilters (which haven't been used yet) with the points of $X$. With these conventions, one can prove (using compactness) that every ultrafilter on $X$ gets identified with a point in the Stone-Cech compactification of $X$. So the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space can be identified with the set of ultrafilters on $X$. Finally, one should verify that the topology is necessarily the one you described.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  2












                  2








                  2





                  $begingroup$

                  Since you already know about the Alexandroff one-point compactification, let me begin by saying that the Stone-Cech compactification is at the other extreme, adding as many points at infinity as possible. To see what that could mean, let's consider some other compactifications of $mathbb R$, starting with the most familiar, the extended real line, obtained by adjoining the two points $+infty$ and $-infty$ at the two ends of the line. Compared with the Alexandroff compactification, we're now distinguishing two different ways of "going to infinity". Some sequences that converged to $infty$ in the Alexandroff compactification fail to converge in the extended real line because part of the sequence goes to the left and part to the right (e.g., $(-1)^nn$).



                  This idea can be extended, to produce "bigger" compactifications. If you visualize $mathbb R$ as embedded in the plane as the graph of the sine function and then take its closure in the extended plane $(mathbb Rcup{+infty,-infty})^2$, you get a compactification with a whole line segment at $+infty$ (and another at $-infty$). Similarly, embedding $mathbb R$ in $3$-dimensional space as a helix, by $xmapsto (x,cos x,sin x)$, we get a compactification with circles at the ends. Proceeding analogously with all bounded continuous functions $mathbb Rtomathbb R$ (in place of $cos$ and $sin$), in a very high-dimensional space (in fact, $2^{aleph_0}$ dimensions), you get one of the standard constructions of the Stone-Cech compactification of $mathbb R$. Roughly speaking, it separates, into different points at infinity, all of the possible "ways to go to $infty$" in $mathbb R$.



                  The analogous story works for discrete spaces $X$ in place of $mathbb R$ (except that I don't need to say "continuous" because all functions on a discrete space are continuous). A point in the Stone-Cech remainder of a discrete space $X$ should be thought of as a "way to go to $infty$" in $X$. But how can such "ways" be described?



                  Well, in any compactification, each point $p$ at infinity is in the closure of the original space $X$, and so we can describe its location relative to $X$ by the trace on $X$ of its neighborhood filter, i.e. by $mathcal F={Ucap X: pintext{interior}(U)}$ (where $U$ refers to subsets of the compactification). Note that $mathcal F$ can't contain any finite subsets of $X$, because such subsets are closed in the compactification (as in any $T_1$ space) and thus disjoint from suitable neighborhoods of any point $p$ at infinity.



                  For the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space $X$, this filter $mathcal F$ must have one additional property, namely that we cannot have two disjoint subsets $A,B$ of $X$ both meeting all the sets in $mathcal F$. The reason is that then "going to infinity" in $A$ and in $B$ would be two different ways to go to infinity, both leading to the same point $p$.



                  This additional property of the filter $mathcal F$ is equivalent to saying that $mathcal F$ is an ultrafilter. So this is how ultrafilters enter the picture of Stone-Cech compactifications of discrete spaces.



                  One then ordinarily continues by saying that, (1) since the filter $mathcal F$ associated with any $p$ at infinity is an ultrafilter, and different $p$'s must correspond to different ultrafilters (in order for the compactification to be Hausdorff), we might as well identify the points $p$ with the ultrafilters $mathcal F$, and (2) for the sake of uniformity, we might as well identify the principal ultrafilters (which haven't been used yet) with the points of $X$. With these conventions, one can prove (using compactness) that every ultrafilter on $X$ gets identified with a point in the Stone-Cech compactification of $X$. So the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space can be identified with the set of ultrafilters on $X$. Finally, one should verify that the topology is necessarily the one you described.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  Since you already know about the Alexandroff one-point compactification, let me begin by saying that the Stone-Cech compactification is at the other extreme, adding as many points at infinity as possible. To see what that could mean, let's consider some other compactifications of $mathbb R$, starting with the most familiar, the extended real line, obtained by adjoining the two points $+infty$ and $-infty$ at the two ends of the line. Compared with the Alexandroff compactification, we're now distinguishing two different ways of "going to infinity". Some sequences that converged to $infty$ in the Alexandroff compactification fail to converge in the extended real line because part of the sequence goes to the left and part to the right (e.g., $(-1)^nn$).



                  This idea can be extended, to produce "bigger" compactifications. If you visualize $mathbb R$ as embedded in the plane as the graph of the sine function and then take its closure in the extended plane $(mathbb Rcup{+infty,-infty})^2$, you get a compactification with a whole line segment at $+infty$ (and another at $-infty$). Similarly, embedding $mathbb R$ in $3$-dimensional space as a helix, by $xmapsto (x,cos x,sin x)$, we get a compactification with circles at the ends. Proceeding analogously with all bounded continuous functions $mathbb Rtomathbb R$ (in place of $cos$ and $sin$), in a very high-dimensional space (in fact, $2^{aleph_0}$ dimensions), you get one of the standard constructions of the Stone-Cech compactification of $mathbb R$. Roughly speaking, it separates, into different points at infinity, all of the possible "ways to go to $infty$" in $mathbb R$.



                  The analogous story works for discrete spaces $X$ in place of $mathbb R$ (except that I don't need to say "continuous" because all functions on a discrete space are continuous). A point in the Stone-Cech remainder of a discrete space $X$ should be thought of as a "way to go to $infty$" in $X$. But how can such "ways" be described?



                  Well, in any compactification, each point $p$ at infinity is in the closure of the original space $X$, and so we can describe its location relative to $X$ by the trace on $X$ of its neighborhood filter, i.e. by $mathcal F={Ucap X: pintext{interior}(U)}$ (where $U$ refers to subsets of the compactification). Note that $mathcal F$ can't contain any finite subsets of $X$, because such subsets are closed in the compactification (as in any $T_1$ space) and thus disjoint from suitable neighborhoods of any point $p$ at infinity.



                  For the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space $X$, this filter $mathcal F$ must have one additional property, namely that we cannot have two disjoint subsets $A,B$ of $X$ both meeting all the sets in $mathcal F$. The reason is that then "going to infinity" in $A$ and in $B$ would be two different ways to go to infinity, both leading to the same point $p$.



                  This additional property of the filter $mathcal F$ is equivalent to saying that $mathcal F$ is an ultrafilter. So this is how ultrafilters enter the picture of Stone-Cech compactifications of discrete spaces.



                  One then ordinarily continues by saying that, (1) since the filter $mathcal F$ associated with any $p$ at infinity is an ultrafilter, and different $p$'s must correspond to different ultrafilters (in order for the compactification to be Hausdorff), we might as well identify the points $p$ with the ultrafilters $mathcal F$, and (2) for the sake of uniformity, we might as well identify the principal ultrafilters (which haven't been used yet) with the points of $X$. With these conventions, one can prove (using compactness) that every ultrafilter on $X$ gets identified with a point in the Stone-Cech compactification of $X$. So the Stone-Cech compactification of a discrete space can be identified with the set of ultrafilters on $X$. Finally, one should verify that the topology is necessarily the one you described.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Jan 26 at 17:12









                  Andreas BlassAndreas Blass

                  50.3k452109




                  50.3k452109























                      2












                      $begingroup$

                      If we have a space $S$ then one can show (it's classical) that $S$ is compact iff every ultrafilter on $S$ has a limit in $S$.



                      So for an infinite discrete space (which has no ultrafilter limits, except for the fixed ultrafilters) we need to add a point to be a limit for each ultrafilter, and $beta(S)$ will be the maximal compactification, so we add a different point for each ultrafilter (the one-point compactification adds just one point for all of them).






                      share|cite|improve this answer









                      $endgroup$


















                        2












                        $begingroup$

                        If we have a space $S$ then one can show (it's classical) that $S$ is compact iff every ultrafilter on $S$ has a limit in $S$.



                        So for an infinite discrete space (which has no ultrafilter limits, except for the fixed ultrafilters) we need to add a point to be a limit for each ultrafilter, and $beta(S)$ will be the maximal compactification, so we add a different point for each ultrafilter (the one-point compactification adds just one point for all of them).






                        share|cite|improve this answer









                        $endgroup$
















                          2












                          2








                          2





                          $begingroup$

                          If we have a space $S$ then one can show (it's classical) that $S$ is compact iff every ultrafilter on $S$ has a limit in $S$.



                          So for an infinite discrete space (which has no ultrafilter limits, except for the fixed ultrafilters) we need to add a point to be a limit for each ultrafilter, and $beta(S)$ will be the maximal compactification, so we add a different point for each ultrafilter (the one-point compactification adds just one point for all of them).






                          share|cite|improve this answer









                          $endgroup$



                          If we have a space $S$ then one can show (it's classical) that $S$ is compact iff every ultrafilter on $S$ has a limit in $S$.



                          So for an infinite discrete space (which has no ultrafilter limits, except for the fixed ultrafilters) we need to add a point to be a limit for each ultrafilter, and $beta(S)$ will be the maximal compactification, so we add a different point for each ultrafilter (the one-point compactification adds just one point for all of them).







                          share|cite|improve this answer












                          share|cite|improve this answer



                          share|cite|improve this answer










                          answered Jan 26 at 15:34









                          Henno BrandsmaHenno Brandsma

                          113k348123




                          113k348123






























                              draft saved

                              draft discarded




















































                              Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                              • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                              But avoid



                              • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                              • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                              Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                              To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                              draft saved


                              draft discarded














                              StackExchange.ready(
                              function () {
                              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3088257%2fintuition-for-the-stone-%25c4%258cech-compactification-via-ultrafilters%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                              }
                              );

                              Post as a guest















                              Required, but never shown





















































                              Required, but never shown














                              Required, but never shown












                              Required, but never shown







                              Required, but never shown

































                              Required, but never shown














                              Required, but never shown












                              Required, but never shown







                              Required, but never shown







                              Popular posts from this blog

                              MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

                              How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

                              in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith