are two different pairs of objects allowed to share the same morphism in a category?












2












$begingroup$


Normally I think of a morphism as belonging to two objects. e.g. for objects $a,b$ I think of a morphism $f$ between $a$ and $b$ as having the "type" $f:ato b$.



But I can't see in the definition of category that a morphism has to be connected specifically to two objects.



Can we have a category with distinct objects $a,b,c,d$ where $Hom(a,b)cap Hom(c,d)neq emptyset$?



example: we could have the morphisms be distances between objects where the objects are elements of a metric space. Then $Hom(a,b)= Hom(c,d)$ if $dist(a,b)=dist(c,d)$.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 28 at 7:24
















2












$begingroup$


Normally I think of a morphism as belonging to two objects. e.g. for objects $a,b$ I think of a morphism $f$ between $a$ and $b$ as having the "type" $f:ato b$.



But I can't see in the definition of category that a morphism has to be connected specifically to two objects.



Can we have a category with distinct objects $a,b,c,d$ where $Hom(a,b)cap Hom(c,d)neq emptyset$?



example: we could have the morphisms be distances between objects where the objects are elements of a metric space. Then $Hom(a,b)= Hom(c,d)$ if $dist(a,b)=dist(c,d)$.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 28 at 7:24














2












2








2


0



$begingroup$


Normally I think of a morphism as belonging to two objects. e.g. for objects $a,b$ I think of a morphism $f$ between $a$ and $b$ as having the "type" $f:ato b$.



But I can't see in the definition of category that a morphism has to be connected specifically to two objects.



Can we have a category with distinct objects $a,b,c,d$ where $Hom(a,b)cap Hom(c,d)neq emptyset$?



example: we could have the morphisms be distances between objects where the objects are elements of a metric space. Then $Hom(a,b)= Hom(c,d)$ if $dist(a,b)=dist(c,d)$.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




Normally I think of a morphism as belonging to two objects. e.g. for objects $a,b$ I think of a morphism $f$ between $a$ and $b$ as having the "type" $f:ato b$.



But I can't see in the definition of category that a morphism has to be connected specifically to two objects.



Can we have a category with distinct objects $a,b,c,d$ where $Hom(a,b)cap Hom(c,d)neq emptyset$?



example: we could have the morphisms be distances between objects where the objects are elements of a metric space. Then $Hom(a,b)= Hom(c,d)$ if $dist(a,b)=dist(c,d)$.







category-theory






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jan 28 at 7:48







user56834

















asked Jan 28 at 7:13









user56834user56834

3,35921253




3,35921253












  • $begingroup$
    I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 28 at 7:24


















  • $begingroup$
    I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
    $endgroup$
    – Lord Shark the Unknown
    Jan 28 at 7:24
















$begingroup$
I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
$endgroup$
– Lord Shark the Unknown
Jan 28 at 7:24




$begingroup$
I like it when arrows in a category have well defined sources and targets....
$endgroup$
– Lord Shark the Unknown
Jan 28 at 7:24










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















5












$begingroup$

It depends on the definition of a category. If a category is defined as a $6$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),text{Mor}(mathcal{C}),text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}},circ_{mathcal{C}},text{id}_{mathcal{C}}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $text{Mor}(mathcal{C})$ are sets (classes) and $text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}colontext{Mor}(mathcal{C})totext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ are mappings, then all morphisms are disjoint and for objects $a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have the following definition of the $hom$-set:
$$
text{hom}_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)={fintext{Mor}(mathcal{C})|text{dom}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=a, text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=b},
$$

so if $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $(a,b)ne(c,d)$, then
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)=varnothing.
$$

Now if your definition of a category is a $4$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(circ_{mathcal{C},a,b,c})_{a,b,cintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(text{id}_{mathcal{C},a})_{aintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ is a set (class) and $(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}$ is a family of sets, then it may happen that
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)nevarnothing.
$$

Moreover, all $hom$-sets may be equal. For example, if $X$ is a set, put $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={*}$ (fixed one-elemented set) for every $x_1,x_2in X$. Then for every $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have:
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)=hom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d).
$$

Your example with metric spaces also works (for a metric space $(X,d)$ we should take $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={d(x_1,x_2)}$; such categories are preorders where all elements are comparable; they are isomorphic to the categories from the previous example).



However, we may define a morphism as a triplet $(a,b,f)$, where $finhom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)$, which turns the latter definition to the former (this is a simple construction, described in Mac Lane's "Categories for the Working Mathematician" at the bottom of the page 27). So it is just a matter of convention.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Jan 28 at 9:38











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3090574%2fare-two-different-pairs-of-objects-allowed-to-share-the-same-morphism-in-a-categ%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









5












$begingroup$

It depends on the definition of a category. If a category is defined as a $6$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),text{Mor}(mathcal{C}),text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}},circ_{mathcal{C}},text{id}_{mathcal{C}}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $text{Mor}(mathcal{C})$ are sets (classes) and $text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}colontext{Mor}(mathcal{C})totext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ are mappings, then all morphisms are disjoint and for objects $a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have the following definition of the $hom$-set:
$$
text{hom}_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)={fintext{Mor}(mathcal{C})|text{dom}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=a, text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=b},
$$

so if $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $(a,b)ne(c,d)$, then
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)=varnothing.
$$

Now if your definition of a category is a $4$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(circ_{mathcal{C},a,b,c})_{a,b,cintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(text{id}_{mathcal{C},a})_{aintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ is a set (class) and $(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}$ is a family of sets, then it may happen that
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)nevarnothing.
$$

Moreover, all $hom$-sets may be equal. For example, if $X$ is a set, put $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={*}$ (fixed one-elemented set) for every $x_1,x_2in X$. Then for every $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have:
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)=hom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d).
$$

Your example with metric spaces also works (for a metric space $(X,d)$ we should take $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={d(x_1,x_2)}$; such categories are preorders where all elements are comparable; they are isomorphic to the categories from the previous example).



However, we may define a morphism as a triplet $(a,b,f)$, where $finhom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)$, which turns the latter definition to the former (this is a simple construction, described in Mac Lane's "Categories for the Working Mathematician" at the bottom of the page 27). So it is just a matter of convention.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Jan 28 at 9:38
















5












$begingroup$

It depends on the definition of a category. If a category is defined as a $6$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),text{Mor}(mathcal{C}),text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}},circ_{mathcal{C}},text{id}_{mathcal{C}}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $text{Mor}(mathcal{C})$ are sets (classes) and $text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}colontext{Mor}(mathcal{C})totext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ are mappings, then all morphisms are disjoint and for objects $a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have the following definition of the $hom$-set:
$$
text{hom}_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)={fintext{Mor}(mathcal{C})|text{dom}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=a, text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=b},
$$

so if $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $(a,b)ne(c,d)$, then
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)=varnothing.
$$

Now if your definition of a category is a $4$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(circ_{mathcal{C},a,b,c})_{a,b,cintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(text{id}_{mathcal{C},a})_{aintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ is a set (class) and $(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}$ is a family of sets, then it may happen that
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)nevarnothing.
$$

Moreover, all $hom$-sets may be equal. For example, if $X$ is a set, put $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={*}$ (fixed one-elemented set) for every $x_1,x_2in X$. Then for every $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have:
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)=hom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d).
$$

Your example with metric spaces also works (for a metric space $(X,d)$ we should take $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={d(x_1,x_2)}$; such categories are preorders where all elements are comparable; they are isomorphic to the categories from the previous example).



However, we may define a morphism as a triplet $(a,b,f)$, where $finhom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)$, which turns the latter definition to the former (this is a simple construction, described in Mac Lane's "Categories for the Working Mathematician" at the bottom of the page 27). So it is just a matter of convention.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Jan 28 at 9:38














5












5








5





$begingroup$

It depends on the definition of a category. If a category is defined as a $6$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),text{Mor}(mathcal{C}),text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}},circ_{mathcal{C}},text{id}_{mathcal{C}}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $text{Mor}(mathcal{C})$ are sets (classes) and $text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}colontext{Mor}(mathcal{C})totext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ are mappings, then all morphisms are disjoint and for objects $a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have the following definition of the $hom$-set:
$$
text{hom}_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)={fintext{Mor}(mathcal{C})|text{dom}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=a, text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=b},
$$

so if $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $(a,b)ne(c,d)$, then
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)=varnothing.
$$

Now if your definition of a category is a $4$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(circ_{mathcal{C},a,b,c})_{a,b,cintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(text{id}_{mathcal{C},a})_{aintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ is a set (class) and $(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}$ is a family of sets, then it may happen that
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)nevarnothing.
$$

Moreover, all $hom$-sets may be equal. For example, if $X$ is a set, put $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={*}$ (fixed one-elemented set) for every $x_1,x_2in X$. Then for every $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have:
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)=hom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d).
$$

Your example with metric spaces also works (for a metric space $(X,d)$ we should take $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={d(x_1,x_2)}$; such categories are preorders where all elements are comparable; they are isomorphic to the categories from the previous example).



However, we may define a morphism as a triplet $(a,b,f)$, where $finhom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)$, which turns the latter definition to the former (this is a simple construction, described in Mac Lane's "Categories for the Working Mathematician" at the bottom of the page 27). So it is just a matter of convention.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



It depends on the definition of a category. If a category is defined as a $6$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),text{Mor}(mathcal{C}),text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}},circ_{mathcal{C}},text{id}_{mathcal{C}}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $text{Mor}(mathcal{C})$ are sets (classes) and $text{dom}_{mathcal{C}},text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}colontext{Mor}(mathcal{C})totext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ are mappings, then all morphisms are disjoint and for objects $a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have the following definition of the $hom$-set:
$$
text{hom}_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)={fintext{Mor}(mathcal{C})|text{dom}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=a, text{cod}_{mathcal{C}}(f)=b},
$$

so if $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ and $(a,b)ne(c,d)$, then
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)=varnothing.
$$

Now if your definition of a category is a $4$-tuple $$mathcal{C}=(text{Obj}(mathcal{C}),(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(circ_{mathcal{C},a,b,c})_{a,b,cintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})},(text{id}_{mathcal{C},a})_{aintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}),$$
where $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ is a set (class) and $(hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b))_{a,bintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})}$ is a family of sets, then it may happen that
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)caphom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d)nevarnothing.
$$

Moreover, all $hom$-sets may be equal. For example, if $X$ is a set, put $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={*}$ (fixed one-elemented set) for every $x_1,x_2in X$. Then for every $a,b,c,dintext{Obj}(mathcal{C})$ we have:
$$
hom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)=hom_{mathcal{C}}(c,d).
$$

Your example with metric spaces also works (for a metric space $(X,d)$ we should take $text{Obj}(mathcal{C})=X$ and $hom_{mathcal{C}}(x_1,x_2)={d(x_1,x_2)}$; such categories are preorders where all elements are comparable; they are isomorphic to the categories from the previous example).



However, we may define a morphism as a triplet $(a,b,f)$, where $finhom_{mathcal{C}}(a,b)$, which turns the latter definition to the former (this is a simple construction, described in Mac Lane's "Categories for the Working Mathematician" at the bottom of the page 27). So it is just a matter of convention.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Jan 28 at 8:54

























answered Jan 28 at 8:48









OskarOskar

3,2031819




3,2031819








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Jan 28 at 9:38














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Jan 28 at 9:38








2




2




$begingroup$
I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 28 at 9:38




$begingroup$
I note for the benefit of the querent that even using the latter definition of category, once you start making any statements about composites you have to choose which composition operation you're applying, which gives a de facto unique source and target to any of the morphisms appearing in a particular statement. So even though you may have distinct hom-sets with a non-empty intersection, any category theoretic statement is going to work as if every morphism had a unique domain and codomain.
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 28 at 9:38


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3090574%2fare-two-different-pairs-of-objects-allowed-to-share-the-same-morphism-in-a-categ%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Can a sorcerer learn a 5th-level spell early by creating spell slots using the Font of Magic feature?

ts Property 'filter' does not exist on type '{}'

Notepad++ export/extract a list of installed plugins