Intuitive notion of negation: implication example












0












$begingroup$


I am bit puzzled with intuitive notion of negating an implication.
Say we have an implication.
If A is true, then B is true.
Say we want to negate it. Not analytically, rather intuitively.



Now, why is following NOT a negation of implication?




If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know).











share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 8:54












  • $begingroup$
    @ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 9:02








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:13












  • $begingroup$
    "We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:17










  • $begingroup$
    @davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:40
















0












$begingroup$


I am bit puzzled with intuitive notion of negating an implication.
Say we have an implication.
If A is true, then B is true.
Say we want to negate it. Not analytically, rather intuitively.



Now, why is following NOT a negation of implication?




If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know).











share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 8:54












  • $begingroup$
    @ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 9:02








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:13












  • $begingroup$
    "We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:17










  • $begingroup$
    @davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:40














0












0








0





$begingroup$


I am bit puzzled with intuitive notion of negating an implication.
Say we have an implication.
If A is true, then B is true.
Say we want to negate it. Not analytically, rather intuitively.



Now, why is following NOT a negation of implication?




If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know).











share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I am bit puzzled with intuitive notion of negating an implication.
Say we have an implication.
If A is true, then B is true.
Say we want to negate it. Not analytically, rather intuitively.



Now, why is following NOT a negation of implication?




If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know).








logic propositional-calculus






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jan 28 at 8:19









davidkdavidk

1




1












  • $begingroup$
    What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 8:54












  • $begingroup$
    @ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 9:02








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:13












  • $begingroup$
    "We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:17










  • $begingroup$
    @davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:40


















  • $begingroup$
    What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 8:54












  • $begingroup$
    @ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 9:02








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:13












  • $begingroup$
    "We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:17










  • $begingroup$
    @davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
    $endgroup$
    – Shubham Johri
    Jan 28 at 9:40
















$begingroup$
What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 8:54






$begingroup$
What you have written is a tautology. '$B$ is either true or not' is a tautology because $B$ has to be either true or false, so the statement is always true. Logically, $Boplusneg B=B+(neg B)=1$. This means you are proposing $Ato1equiv1$.
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 8:54














$begingroup$
@ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
$endgroup$
– davidk
Jan 28 at 9:02






$begingroup$
@ShubhamJohri consider if A is true then B is sometimes true sometimes false, I know this kind of things might not be studied in logic, but I am trying to illustrate what I meant. That maybe negation is not only when A is true and B is false, but maybe if A is true and you don't know status of B that is also negation.
$endgroup$
– davidk
Jan 28 at 9:02






1




1




$begingroup$
How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 9:13






$begingroup$
How exactly do you define 'sometimes'? More formally, do you mean to say there is a third (or more) variable(s), say $C$, that controls the state of $B$ other than $A$?
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 9:13














$begingroup$
"We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
$endgroup$
– NoChance
Jan 28 at 9:17




$begingroup$
"We don't know" is open whereas in fact it is either true/false or inconsistent, or can't be known....each has its own treatement
$endgroup$
– NoChance
Jan 28 at 9:17












$begingroup$
@davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 9:40




$begingroup$
@davidk I think you are misinterpreting negation. $neg(Ato B)$ is defined to be true whenever $Ato B$ is false and vice-versa. The trueness of the statement dictates the trueness of its negation. Stating $Ato B$ locks the trueness of the statement $neg(Ato B)$ for all the possible true-false combinations for $A,B$, leaving no room for the uncertainty 'we don't know'.
$endgroup$
– Shubham Johri
Jan 28 at 9:40










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















1












$begingroup$

The conditional $A to B$ does not mean :




"If A is true, then B is true".




The truth table for the conditional has four cases, and only one of them has FALSE as "output".



Thus, considering the negation of $A to B$, we want that it is TRUE exactly when the original one is FALSE.



I.e. $lnot (A to B)$ must be TRUE exactly when $A$ is TRUE and $B$ is FALSE.



This means that the negation of "If A is true, then B is true" is equivalent to :




"A and not B".






Another approach is : consider that $A to B$ is TRUE either when $A$ is FALSE, or when $A$ is TRUE also $B$ is.





There are many discussion about the use of conditional in natural languages and its counterpart in logic; see e.g. the so-called Paradoxes of material implication.



The Material implication of classical propositional calculus is defined through its truth table and thus it is a "simplified model" of the way natural language works.



Its usefulness in formalizing many mathematical (and not only) arguments is the only reason to use it in formal contexts.







Quite different is the case when "implication" means Logical consequence.



We have that $A vDash B$ when there is no interpretations that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.



In this case, we have that if $A$ is True, we can assert that also $B$ is.



On the other hand, if $A$ is False, then $B$ can be either True or False.



If we follow this approach, what is the negation of $A vDash B$ ?



It is :




there is at least one interpretation that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 8:31












  • $begingroup$
    Very good points made here. Thank you.
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:15










  • $begingroup$
    The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
    $endgroup$
    – Dan Christensen
    Jan 28 at 13:42



















0












$begingroup$

What does $A$ implies $B$ mean in classical logic? In the context of a logical proof, it means only that, at the moment, it is not the case that both A is true and B is false. Symbolically:




$A implies B space equiv space neg (A land neg B)$




This is often given as a definition in textbooks, but it can also be derived using other rules of natural deduction including other elementary properties of logical implication.



Note that there is no suggestion here of cause and effect, or the passage of time. It may help to think of it is as a single snap shot of reality. This is true of classical logic in general, and nearly all of modern mathematics. For the most part, causality and the passage of time are in the realms of science, not mathematics.



Now, the negation of $Aimplies B$ is obviously $Aland neg B$.



In words: $A$ is true and $B$ is false.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3090607%2fintuitive-notion-of-negation-implication-example%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    1












    $begingroup$

    The conditional $A to B$ does not mean :




    "If A is true, then B is true".




    The truth table for the conditional has four cases, and only one of them has FALSE as "output".



    Thus, considering the negation of $A to B$, we want that it is TRUE exactly when the original one is FALSE.



    I.e. $lnot (A to B)$ must be TRUE exactly when $A$ is TRUE and $B$ is FALSE.



    This means that the negation of "If A is true, then B is true" is equivalent to :




    "A and not B".






    Another approach is : consider that $A to B$ is TRUE either when $A$ is FALSE, or when $A$ is TRUE also $B$ is.





    There are many discussion about the use of conditional in natural languages and its counterpart in logic; see e.g. the so-called Paradoxes of material implication.



    The Material implication of classical propositional calculus is defined through its truth table and thus it is a "simplified model" of the way natural language works.



    Its usefulness in formalizing many mathematical (and not only) arguments is the only reason to use it in formal contexts.







    Quite different is the case when "implication" means Logical consequence.



    We have that $A vDash B$ when there is no interpretations that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.



    In this case, we have that if $A$ is True, we can assert that also $B$ is.



    On the other hand, if $A$ is False, then $B$ can be either True or False.



    If we follow this approach, what is the negation of $A vDash B$ ?



    It is :




    there is at least one interpretation that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
      $endgroup$
      – davidk
      Jan 28 at 8:31












    • $begingroup$
      Very good points made here. Thank you.
      $endgroup$
      – NoChance
      Jan 28 at 9:15










    • $begingroup$
      The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
      $endgroup$
      – Dan Christensen
      Jan 28 at 13:42
















    1












    $begingroup$

    The conditional $A to B$ does not mean :




    "If A is true, then B is true".




    The truth table for the conditional has four cases, and only one of them has FALSE as "output".



    Thus, considering the negation of $A to B$, we want that it is TRUE exactly when the original one is FALSE.



    I.e. $lnot (A to B)$ must be TRUE exactly when $A$ is TRUE and $B$ is FALSE.



    This means that the negation of "If A is true, then B is true" is equivalent to :




    "A and not B".






    Another approach is : consider that $A to B$ is TRUE either when $A$ is FALSE, or when $A$ is TRUE also $B$ is.





    There are many discussion about the use of conditional in natural languages and its counterpart in logic; see e.g. the so-called Paradoxes of material implication.



    The Material implication of classical propositional calculus is defined through its truth table and thus it is a "simplified model" of the way natural language works.



    Its usefulness in formalizing many mathematical (and not only) arguments is the only reason to use it in formal contexts.







    Quite different is the case when "implication" means Logical consequence.



    We have that $A vDash B$ when there is no interpretations that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.



    In this case, we have that if $A$ is True, we can assert that also $B$ is.



    On the other hand, if $A$ is False, then $B$ can be either True or False.



    If we follow this approach, what is the negation of $A vDash B$ ?



    It is :




    there is at least one interpretation that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
      $endgroup$
      – davidk
      Jan 28 at 8:31












    • $begingroup$
      Very good points made here. Thank you.
      $endgroup$
      – NoChance
      Jan 28 at 9:15










    • $begingroup$
      The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
      $endgroup$
      – Dan Christensen
      Jan 28 at 13:42














    1












    1








    1





    $begingroup$

    The conditional $A to B$ does not mean :




    "If A is true, then B is true".




    The truth table for the conditional has four cases, and only one of them has FALSE as "output".



    Thus, considering the negation of $A to B$, we want that it is TRUE exactly when the original one is FALSE.



    I.e. $lnot (A to B)$ must be TRUE exactly when $A$ is TRUE and $B$ is FALSE.



    This means that the negation of "If A is true, then B is true" is equivalent to :




    "A and not B".






    Another approach is : consider that $A to B$ is TRUE either when $A$ is FALSE, or when $A$ is TRUE also $B$ is.





    There are many discussion about the use of conditional in natural languages and its counterpart in logic; see e.g. the so-called Paradoxes of material implication.



    The Material implication of classical propositional calculus is defined through its truth table and thus it is a "simplified model" of the way natural language works.



    Its usefulness in formalizing many mathematical (and not only) arguments is the only reason to use it in formal contexts.







    Quite different is the case when "implication" means Logical consequence.



    We have that $A vDash B$ when there is no interpretations that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.



    In this case, we have that if $A$ is True, we can assert that also $B$ is.



    On the other hand, if $A$ is False, then $B$ can be either True or False.



    If we follow this approach, what is the negation of $A vDash B$ ?



    It is :




    there is at least one interpretation that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.







    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    The conditional $A to B$ does not mean :




    "If A is true, then B is true".




    The truth table for the conditional has four cases, and only one of them has FALSE as "output".



    Thus, considering the negation of $A to B$, we want that it is TRUE exactly when the original one is FALSE.



    I.e. $lnot (A to B)$ must be TRUE exactly when $A$ is TRUE and $B$ is FALSE.



    This means that the negation of "If A is true, then B is true" is equivalent to :




    "A and not B".






    Another approach is : consider that $A to B$ is TRUE either when $A$ is FALSE, or when $A$ is TRUE also $B$ is.





    There are many discussion about the use of conditional in natural languages and its counterpart in logic; see e.g. the so-called Paradoxes of material implication.



    The Material implication of classical propositional calculus is defined through its truth table and thus it is a "simplified model" of the way natural language works.



    Its usefulness in formalizing many mathematical (and not only) arguments is the only reason to use it in formal contexts.







    Quite different is the case when "implication" means Logical consequence.



    We have that $A vDash B$ when there is no interpretations that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.



    In this case, we have that if $A$ is True, we can assert that also $B$ is.



    On the other hand, if $A$ is False, then $B$ can be either True or False.



    If we follow this approach, what is the negation of $A vDash B$ ?



    It is :




    there is at least one interpretation that makes $A$ True and $B$ False.








    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jan 28 at 11:52

























    answered Jan 28 at 8:26









    Mauro ALLEGRANZAMauro ALLEGRANZA

    67.5k449117




    67.5k449117












    • $begingroup$
      You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
      $endgroup$
      – davidk
      Jan 28 at 8:31












    • $begingroup$
      Very good points made here. Thank you.
      $endgroup$
      – NoChance
      Jan 28 at 9:15










    • $begingroup$
      The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
      $endgroup$
      – Dan Christensen
      Jan 28 at 13:42


















    • $begingroup$
      You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
      $endgroup$
      – davidk
      Jan 28 at 8:31












    • $begingroup$
      Very good points made here. Thank you.
      $endgroup$
      – NoChance
      Jan 28 at 9:15










    • $begingroup$
      The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
      $endgroup$
      – Dan Christensen
      Jan 28 at 13:42
















    $begingroup$
    You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 8:31






    $begingroup$
    You answered analytically again, mine was maybe more philosophical in nature, why is: "If A is true, then B is either true or not (we don't know)." NOT a negation of implication, on a intuitive level, because it seems it could be.
    $endgroup$
    – davidk
    Jan 28 at 8:31














    $begingroup$
    Very good points made here. Thank you.
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:15




    $begingroup$
    Very good points made here. Thank you.
    $endgroup$
    – NoChance
    Jan 28 at 9:15












    $begingroup$
    The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
    $endgroup$
    – Dan Christensen
    Jan 28 at 13:42




    $begingroup$
    The so-called paradoxes of material implications are the inevitable consequence of simple, self-evident rules of natural deduction: 1. Conditional proof ($implies$ intro), 2. Proof by contradiction ($neg$ intro), 3. Join statements ($land$ Intro), 4. Split statements ($land$ elim), 5. Double Negation ($neg neg$ elim).
    $endgroup$
    – Dan Christensen
    Jan 28 at 13:42











    0












    $begingroup$

    What does $A$ implies $B$ mean in classical logic? In the context of a logical proof, it means only that, at the moment, it is not the case that both A is true and B is false. Symbolically:




    $A implies B space equiv space neg (A land neg B)$




    This is often given as a definition in textbooks, but it can also be derived using other rules of natural deduction including other elementary properties of logical implication.



    Note that there is no suggestion here of cause and effect, or the passage of time. It may help to think of it is as a single snap shot of reality. This is true of classical logic in general, and nearly all of modern mathematics. For the most part, causality and the passage of time are in the realms of science, not mathematics.



    Now, the negation of $Aimplies B$ is obviously $Aland neg B$.



    In words: $A$ is true and $B$ is false.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$


















      0












      $begingroup$

      What does $A$ implies $B$ mean in classical logic? In the context of a logical proof, it means only that, at the moment, it is not the case that both A is true and B is false. Symbolically:




      $A implies B space equiv space neg (A land neg B)$




      This is often given as a definition in textbooks, but it can also be derived using other rules of natural deduction including other elementary properties of logical implication.



      Note that there is no suggestion here of cause and effect, or the passage of time. It may help to think of it is as a single snap shot of reality. This is true of classical logic in general, and nearly all of modern mathematics. For the most part, causality and the passage of time are in the realms of science, not mathematics.



      Now, the negation of $Aimplies B$ is obviously $Aland neg B$.



      In words: $A$ is true and $B$ is false.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$
















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        What does $A$ implies $B$ mean in classical logic? In the context of a logical proof, it means only that, at the moment, it is not the case that both A is true and B is false. Symbolically:




        $A implies B space equiv space neg (A land neg B)$




        This is often given as a definition in textbooks, but it can also be derived using other rules of natural deduction including other elementary properties of logical implication.



        Note that there is no suggestion here of cause and effect, or the passage of time. It may help to think of it is as a single snap shot of reality. This is true of classical logic in general, and nearly all of modern mathematics. For the most part, causality and the passage of time are in the realms of science, not mathematics.



        Now, the negation of $Aimplies B$ is obviously $Aland neg B$.



        In words: $A$ is true and $B$ is false.






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$



        What does $A$ implies $B$ mean in classical logic? In the context of a logical proof, it means only that, at the moment, it is not the case that both A is true and B is false. Symbolically:




        $A implies B space equiv space neg (A land neg B)$




        This is often given as a definition in textbooks, but it can also be derived using other rules of natural deduction including other elementary properties of logical implication.



        Note that there is no suggestion here of cause and effect, or the passage of time. It may help to think of it is as a single snap shot of reality. This is true of classical logic in general, and nearly all of modern mathematics. For the most part, causality and the passage of time are in the realms of science, not mathematics.



        Now, the negation of $Aimplies B$ is obviously $Aland neg B$.



        In words: $A$ is true and $B$ is false.







        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited Jan 28 at 18:15

























        answered Jan 28 at 13:27









        Dan ChristensenDan Christensen

        8,66321835




        8,66321835






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3090607%2fintuitive-notion-of-negation-implication-example%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Can a sorcerer learn a 5th-level spell early by creating spell slots using the Font of Magic feature?

            ts Property 'filter' does not exist on type '{}'

            Notepad++ export/extract a list of installed plugins