Finding a colimit in the category of presheaves
$begingroup$
I have the following problem as part of my exam preporation and I need an idea how to approach it at least:
Let $mathfrak C$ be a small category and $F: mathfrak C^{opp} rightarrow mathfrak S et$ be a presheaf. Lets constract new category $mathfrak F$ as follows: $operatorname{Ob} mathfrak F = sqcup_{X in operatorname{Ob} mathfrak C} F(X) $ (disjoint union of all object images under the action of functor $F$) and for all $x in F(X)$ and $y in F(Y)$ $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ consitst of all arrows $phi in operatorname{Hom}_{mathfrak C} (X, Y)$ such that $F phi (y) = x$.
Find colimit of the diagram $D: mathfrak F rightarrow mathfrak F unc(mathfrak C^{opp}, mathfrak Set)$ which maps object $x$ (which is also an element of $F(X)$) to presheaf $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak C (-, X)$ and arrow $phi$ from $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ to natural transformation $ phi_*$ of left multiplication on $phi$.
Thanks!
category-theory limits-colimits
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I have the following problem as part of my exam preporation and I need an idea how to approach it at least:
Let $mathfrak C$ be a small category and $F: mathfrak C^{opp} rightarrow mathfrak S et$ be a presheaf. Lets constract new category $mathfrak F$ as follows: $operatorname{Ob} mathfrak F = sqcup_{X in operatorname{Ob} mathfrak C} F(X) $ (disjoint union of all object images under the action of functor $F$) and for all $x in F(X)$ and $y in F(Y)$ $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ consitst of all arrows $phi in operatorname{Hom}_{mathfrak C} (X, Y)$ such that $F phi (y) = x$.
Find colimit of the diagram $D: mathfrak F rightarrow mathfrak F unc(mathfrak C^{opp}, mathfrak Set)$ which maps object $x$ (which is also an element of $F(X)$) to presheaf $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak C (-, X)$ and arrow $phi$ from $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ to natural transformation $ phi_*$ of left multiplication on $phi$.
Thanks!
category-theory limits-colimits
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I have the following problem as part of my exam preporation and I need an idea how to approach it at least:
Let $mathfrak C$ be a small category and $F: mathfrak C^{opp} rightarrow mathfrak S et$ be a presheaf. Lets constract new category $mathfrak F$ as follows: $operatorname{Ob} mathfrak F = sqcup_{X in operatorname{Ob} mathfrak C} F(X) $ (disjoint union of all object images under the action of functor $F$) and for all $x in F(X)$ and $y in F(Y)$ $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ consitst of all arrows $phi in operatorname{Hom}_{mathfrak C} (X, Y)$ such that $F phi (y) = x$.
Find colimit of the diagram $D: mathfrak F rightarrow mathfrak F unc(mathfrak C^{opp}, mathfrak Set)$ which maps object $x$ (which is also an element of $F(X)$) to presheaf $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak C (-, X)$ and arrow $phi$ from $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ to natural transformation $ phi_*$ of left multiplication on $phi$.
Thanks!
category-theory limits-colimits
$endgroup$
I have the following problem as part of my exam preporation and I need an idea how to approach it at least:
Let $mathfrak C$ be a small category and $F: mathfrak C^{opp} rightarrow mathfrak S et$ be a presheaf. Lets constract new category $mathfrak F$ as follows: $operatorname{Ob} mathfrak F = sqcup_{X in operatorname{Ob} mathfrak C} F(X) $ (disjoint union of all object images under the action of functor $F$) and for all $x in F(X)$ and $y in F(Y)$ $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ consitst of all arrows $phi in operatorname{Hom}_{mathfrak C} (X, Y)$ such that $F phi (y) = x$.
Find colimit of the diagram $D: mathfrak F rightarrow mathfrak F unc(mathfrak C^{opp}, mathfrak Set)$ which maps object $x$ (which is also an element of $F(X)$) to presheaf $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak C (-, X)$ and arrow $phi$ from $operatorname{Hom}_mathfrak F (x, y)$ to natural transformation $ phi_*$ of left multiplication on $phi$.
Thanks!
category-theory limits-colimits
category-theory limits-colimits
asked Jan 20 at 17:01
Gleb ChiliGleb Chili
45428
45428
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09
add a comment |
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
It is going to turn out that the colimit of the diagram $D$ is just going to be $F$ itself, due to the Yoneda lemma.
We define a co-cone $alpha$ under $D$ by setting $alpha_{(x,X)}:D(x,X)to F$ to be the unique natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ that sends $id_X$ to $xin F(X)$. To show that this is natural, consider that for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$, we need $$alpha_{(y,Y)}circhom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)},$$ and by the Yoneda lemma it is sufficient to say that the left hand composite sends $id_X$ to $x$. First, $hom(X,f)(id_X)=finhom(X,Y)$; then because $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_Y(id_Y)=y$$ it must be the case that $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_X(f)=F(f)(y).$$ But since $f$ was a morphism $(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$, this means that $F(f)(y)=x$. This shows that $alpha$ is a co-cone as desired.
(Because it's easy to get lost in the subscripts, remember that $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is a natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$, which has as its component at each $Yinmathfrak{C}^{op}$ the function $(alpha_{(x,X)})_Y:hom(Y,X)to F(Y)$.)
To show that this is a colimit, assume that you have a co-cone $beta$ under $D$ to another presheaf $G$. It will again be the case that each component $beta_{(x,X)}:hom(-,X)to G$ picks out a unique $$g_{x,X}=(beta_{(x,X)})_X(id_X)in G(X)$$ by the Yoneda lemma. What you wish to show is that the collection of functions ${gamma_X}_{Xinmathfrak{C}^{op}}$ defined by $$gamma_X(x)=g_{x,X}$$ defines a natural transformation $gamma:Fto G$, and does so uniquely. In this case, "uniquely" means that for each $(x,X)$, the morphisms $gamma_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$ are equal to $beta_{(x,X)}$; and conversely, given any natural transformation $chi:Fto G$, that the co-cone $Dto G$ whose components at $(x,X)$ are $chi_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$, simply gives back $chi$ when fed to the above construction. This is a mouthful, but it's actually quite simple (though not short) to show.
Hopefully this helps!
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3080823%2ffinding-a-colimit-in-the-category-of-presheaves%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
It is going to turn out that the colimit of the diagram $D$ is just going to be $F$ itself, due to the Yoneda lemma.
We define a co-cone $alpha$ under $D$ by setting $alpha_{(x,X)}:D(x,X)to F$ to be the unique natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ that sends $id_X$ to $xin F(X)$. To show that this is natural, consider that for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$, we need $$alpha_{(y,Y)}circhom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)},$$ and by the Yoneda lemma it is sufficient to say that the left hand composite sends $id_X$ to $x$. First, $hom(X,f)(id_X)=finhom(X,Y)$; then because $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_Y(id_Y)=y$$ it must be the case that $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_X(f)=F(f)(y).$$ But since $f$ was a morphism $(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$, this means that $F(f)(y)=x$. This shows that $alpha$ is a co-cone as desired.
(Because it's easy to get lost in the subscripts, remember that $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is a natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$, which has as its component at each $Yinmathfrak{C}^{op}$ the function $(alpha_{(x,X)})_Y:hom(Y,X)to F(Y)$.)
To show that this is a colimit, assume that you have a co-cone $beta$ under $D$ to another presheaf $G$. It will again be the case that each component $beta_{(x,X)}:hom(-,X)to G$ picks out a unique $$g_{x,X}=(beta_{(x,X)})_X(id_X)in G(X)$$ by the Yoneda lemma. What you wish to show is that the collection of functions ${gamma_X}_{Xinmathfrak{C}^{op}}$ defined by $$gamma_X(x)=g_{x,X}$$ defines a natural transformation $gamma:Fto G$, and does so uniquely. In this case, "uniquely" means that for each $(x,X)$, the morphisms $gamma_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$ are equal to $beta_{(x,X)}$; and conversely, given any natural transformation $chi:Fto G$, that the co-cone $Dto G$ whose components at $(x,X)$ are $chi_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$, simply gives back $chi$ when fed to the above construction. This is a mouthful, but it's actually quite simple (though not short) to show.
Hopefully this helps!
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It is going to turn out that the colimit of the diagram $D$ is just going to be $F$ itself, due to the Yoneda lemma.
We define a co-cone $alpha$ under $D$ by setting $alpha_{(x,X)}:D(x,X)to F$ to be the unique natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ that sends $id_X$ to $xin F(X)$. To show that this is natural, consider that for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$, we need $$alpha_{(y,Y)}circhom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)},$$ and by the Yoneda lemma it is sufficient to say that the left hand composite sends $id_X$ to $x$. First, $hom(X,f)(id_X)=finhom(X,Y)$; then because $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_Y(id_Y)=y$$ it must be the case that $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_X(f)=F(f)(y).$$ But since $f$ was a morphism $(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$, this means that $F(f)(y)=x$. This shows that $alpha$ is a co-cone as desired.
(Because it's easy to get lost in the subscripts, remember that $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is a natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$, which has as its component at each $Yinmathfrak{C}^{op}$ the function $(alpha_{(x,X)})_Y:hom(Y,X)to F(Y)$.)
To show that this is a colimit, assume that you have a co-cone $beta$ under $D$ to another presheaf $G$. It will again be the case that each component $beta_{(x,X)}:hom(-,X)to G$ picks out a unique $$g_{x,X}=(beta_{(x,X)})_X(id_X)in G(X)$$ by the Yoneda lemma. What you wish to show is that the collection of functions ${gamma_X}_{Xinmathfrak{C}^{op}}$ defined by $$gamma_X(x)=g_{x,X}$$ defines a natural transformation $gamma:Fto G$, and does so uniquely. In this case, "uniquely" means that for each $(x,X)$, the morphisms $gamma_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$ are equal to $beta_{(x,X)}$; and conversely, given any natural transformation $chi:Fto G$, that the co-cone $Dto G$ whose components at $(x,X)$ are $chi_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$, simply gives back $chi$ when fed to the above construction. This is a mouthful, but it's actually quite simple (though not short) to show.
Hopefully this helps!
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It is going to turn out that the colimit of the diagram $D$ is just going to be $F$ itself, due to the Yoneda lemma.
We define a co-cone $alpha$ under $D$ by setting $alpha_{(x,X)}:D(x,X)to F$ to be the unique natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ that sends $id_X$ to $xin F(X)$. To show that this is natural, consider that for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$, we need $$alpha_{(y,Y)}circhom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)},$$ and by the Yoneda lemma it is sufficient to say that the left hand composite sends $id_X$ to $x$. First, $hom(X,f)(id_X)=finhom(X,Y)$; then because $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_Y(id_Y)=y$$ it must be the case that $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_X(f)=F(f)(y).$$ But since $f$ was a morphism $(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$, this means that $F(f)(y)=x$. This shows that $alpha$ is a co-cone as desired.
(Because it's easy to get lost in the subscripts, remember that $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is a natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$, which has as its component at each $Yinmathfrak{C}^{op}$ the function $(alpha_{(x,X)})_Y:hom(Y,X)to F(Y)$.)
To show that this is a colimit, assume that you have a co-cone $beta$ under $D$ to another presheaf $G$. It will again be the case that each component $beta_{(x,X)}:hom(-,X)to G$ picks out a unique $$g_{x,X}=(beta_{(x,X)})_X(id_X)in G(X)$$ by the Yoneda lemma. What you wish to show is that the collection of functions ${gamma_X}_{Xinmathfrak{C}^{op}}$ defined by $$gamma_X(x)=g_{x,X}$$ defines a natural transformation $gamma:Fto G$, and does so uniquely. In this case, "uniquely" means that for each $(x,X)$, the morphisms $gamma_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$ are equal to $beta_{(x,X)}$; and conversely, given any natural transformation $chi:Fto G$, that the co-cone $Dto G$ whose components at $(x,X)$ are $chi_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$, simply gives back $chi$ when fed to the above construction. This is a mouthful, but it's actually quite simple (though not short) to show.
Hopefully this helps!
$endgroup$
It is going to turn out that the colimit of the diagram $D$ is just going to be $F$ itself, due to the Yoneda lemma.
We define a co-cone $alpha$ under $D$ by setting $alpha_{(x,X)}:D(x,X)to F$ to be the unique natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ that sends $id_X$ to $xin F(X)$. To show that this is natural, consider that for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$, we need $$alpha_{(y,Y)}circhom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)},$$ and by the Yoneda lemma it is sufficient to say that the left hand composite sends $id_X$ to $x$. First, $hom(X,f)(id_X)=finhom(X,Y)$; then because $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_Y(id_Y)=y$$ it must be the case that $$(alpha_{(y,Y)})_X(f)=F(f)(y).$$ But since $f$ was a morphism $(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$, this means that $F(f)(y)=x$. This shows that $alpha$ is a co-cone as desired.
(Because it's easy to get lost in the subscripts, remember that $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is a natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$, which has as its component at each $Yinmathfrak{C}^{op}$ the function $(alpha_{(x,X)})_Y:hom(Y,X)to F(Y)$.)
To show that this is a colimit, assume that you have a co-cone $beta$ under $D$ to another presheaf $G$. It will again be the case that each component $beta_{(x,X)}:hom(-,X)to G$ picks out a unique $$g_{x,X}=(beta_{(x,X)})_X(id_X)in G(X)$$ by the Yoneda lemma. What you wish to show is that the collection of functions ${gamma_X}_{Xinmathfrak{C}^{op}}$ defined by $$gamma_X(x)=g_{x,X}$$ defines a natural transformation $gamma:Fto G$, and does so uniquely. In this case, "uniquely" means that for each $(x,X)$, the morphisms $gamma_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$ are equal to $beta_{(x,X)}$; and conversely, given any natural transformation $chi:Fto G$, that the co-cone $Dto G$ whose components at $(x,X)$ are $chi_Xcircalpha_{(x,X)}$, simply gives back $chi$ when fed to the above construction. This is a mouthful, but it's actually quite simple (though not short) to show.
Hopefully this helps!
edited Jan 21 at 22:45
answered Jan 21 at 22:18


Malice VidrineMalice Vidrine
6,17921123
6,17921123
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3080823%2ffinding-a-colimit-in-the-category-of-presheaves%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
As a hint, think about the Yoneda lemma: the objects of $mathfrak{F}$ correspond to natural transformations $mathrm{Hom}(-,X)to F$, and the defining condition on $mathfrak{F}$'s hom-sets means for $f:(x,X)to (y,Y)$ in $mathfrak{F}$ , we have $alpha _{(y,Y)}hom(-,f)=alpha_{(x,X)}$ (where $alpha_{(x,X)}$ is the natural transformation $hom(-,X)to F$ corresponding to $xin F(x)$).
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Jan 20 at 17:26
$begingroup$
@MaliceVidrine May I ask you for more detailes? I still can't see what I have to do with it.
$endgroup$
– Gleb Chili
Jan 21 at 21:09