Is it possible to eliminate completly the type $1$ error risk?
$begingroup$
I was reading here about type $1$ and type $2$ errors and I have a question.
Since "No hypothesis test is 100% certain. Because the test is based on probabilities, there is always a chance of making an incorrect conclusion." Does this mean that is impossible to lower the risk so that the risk to make a type $1$ eror is actually $0$?
Or can there be a way to obtain the risk of making a type $1$ error $0$?
What about the type $2$ error? Is it possible to make it's risk $0$?
I am looking forward for a more detailed/rigurous answer for this and not necesary depending on a specific problem (A more general case).
statistics hypothesis-testing
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I was reading here about type $1$ and type $2$ errors and I have a question.
Since "No hypothesis test is 100% certain. Because the test is based on probabilities, there is always a chance of making an incorrect conclusion." Does this mean that is impossible to lower the risk so that the risk to make a type $1$ eror is actually $0$?
Or can there be a way to obtain the risk of making a type $1$ error $0$?
What about the type $2$ error? Is it possible to make it's risk $0$?
I am looking forward for a more detailed/rigurous answer for this and not necesary depending on a specific problem (A more general case).
statistics hypothesis-testing
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I was reading here about type $1$ and type $2$ errors and I have a question.
Since "No hypothesis test is 100% certain. Because the test is based on probabilities, there is always a chance of making an incorrect conclusion." Does this mean that is impossible to lower the risk so that the risk to make a type $1$ eror is actually $0$?
Or can there be a way to obtain the risk of making a type $1$ error $0$?
What about the type $2$ error? Is it possible to make it's risk $0$?
I am looking forward for a more detailed/rigurous answer for this and not necesary depending on a specific problem (A more general case).
statistics hypothesis-testing
$endgroup$
I was reading here about type $1$ and type $2$ errors and I have a question.
Since "No hypothesis test is 100% certain. Because the test is based on probabilities, there is always a chance of making an incorrect conclusion." Does this mean that is impossible to lower the risk so that the risk to make a type $1$ eror is actually $0$?
Or can there be a way to obtain the risk of making a type $1$ error $0$?
What about the type $2$ error? Is it possible to make it's risk $0$?
I am looking forward for a more detailed/rigurous answer for this and not necesary depending on a specific problem (A more general case).
statistics hypothesis-testing
statistics hypothesis-testing
edited Feb 1 at 21:40
asked Jan 30 at 21:47
user625055
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54
add a comment |
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Usually there is no way for the risk of making a Type I error to be $0$. Suppose that you have a test statistic for your null hypothesis and you set a threshold, saying "If the test statistic exceeds this threshold then I will reject the null hypothesis". If there is any possibility that the test statistic will exceed this threshold under the null hypothesis then the Type I error rate will be greater than $0$.
For example, suppose that $X_1, dots, X_n$ are known to be independent and identically distributed random variables with each $X_i sim N(mu, 1)$ (mean $mu$, variance $1$), where the mean is unknown. Let the null hypothesis be that $mu = 0$ and let the alternative be that $mu > 0$. We consider the test statistic $bar{X} = frac{1}{n} sum_{i = 1}^n X_i$. Under the null hypothesis we have $bar{X} sim N(0, 1/n)$ (mean $0$, variance $1/n$). If you say, "I will reject the null hypothesis if $bar{X}$ exceeds threshold $T$" then no matter how large $T$ is (as long as it is finite), we have $P(bar{X} > T) > 0$ and this is our probability of Type I error. If $T = infty$ then you are in the trivial case where your Type I error is $0$ because it is impossible for you to reject the null hypothesis under any circumstances.
Occasionally you can have cases where you can certainly reject the null hypothesis. E.g. if your null hypothesis is that $T$ is an upper bound for observations $X_1, dots, X_n$ and your alternative is that the true upper bound is higher than $T$, then as soon as you observe some $X_i > T$ then you can reject the null hypothesis with no chance of Type I error, since it would be impossible to see $X_i > T$ under the null hypothesis.
The same argument applies for Type II error: if there is any possibility that the data will look like they were generated under the assumptions of the null hypothesis when they are actually generated from the alternative, then you have a non-zero probability of Type II error.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
With these triangular distributions, if you set your criterion as shown by the red dashed line, you will never make a mistake by categorizing a member of the blue category as a member of the tan category.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If you want absolutely to avoid type I error in a pregnancy test, always say "you are not pregnant"
Edit: you will find more about the picture and type I and II errors here:
http://www.sethspielman.org/courses/geog5023/r_examples/Type_I_and_II_Errors.html
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3094161%2fis-it-possible-to-eliminate-completly-the-type-1-error-risk%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Usually there is no way for the risk of making a Type I error to be $0$. Suppose that you have a test statistic for your null hypothesis and you set a threshold, saying "If the test statistic exceeds this threshold then I will reject the null hypothesis". If there is any possibility that the test statistic will exceed this threshold under the null hypothesis then the Type I error rate will be greater than $0$.
For example, suppose that $X_1, dots, X_n$ are known to be independent and identically distributed random variables with each $X_i sim N(mu, 1)$ (mean $mu$, variance $1$), where the mean is unknown. Let the null hypothesis be that $mu = 0$ and let the alternative be that $mu > 0$. We consider the test statistic $bar{X} = frac{1}{n} sum_{i = 1}^n X_i$. Under the null hypothesis we have $bar{X} sim N(0, 1/n)$ (mean $0$, variance $1/n$). If you say, "I will reject the null hypothesis if $bar{X}$ exceeds threshold $T$" then no matter how large $T$ is (as long as it is finite), we have $P(bar{X} > T) > 0$ and this is our probability of Type I error. If $T = infty$ then you are in the trivial case where your Type I error is $0$ because it is impossible for you to reject the null hypothesis under any circumstances.
Occasionally you can have cases where you can certainly reject the null hypothesis. E.g. if your null hypothesis is that $T$ is an upper bound for observations $X_1, dots, X_n$ and your alternative is that the true upper bound is higher than $T$, then as soon as you observe some $X_i > T$ then you can reject the null hypothesis with no chance of Type I error, since it would be impossible to see $X_i > T$ under the null hypothesis.
The same argument applies for Type II error: if there is any possibility that the data will look like they were generated under the assumptions of the null hypothesis when they are actually generated from the alternative, then you have a non-zero probability of Type II error.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Usually there is no way for the risk of making a Type I error to be $0$. Suppose that you have a test statistic for your null hypothesis and you set a threshold, saying "If the test statistic exceeds this threshold then I will reject the null hypothesis". If there is any possibility that the test statistic will exceed this threshold under the null hypothesis then the Type I error rate will be greater than $0$.
For example, suppose that $X_1, dots, X_n$ are known to be independent and identically distributed random variables with each $X_i sim N(mu, 1)$ (mean $mu$, variance $1$), where the mean is unknown. Let the null hypothesis be that $mu = 0$ and let the alternative be that $mu > 0$. We consider the test statistic $bar{X} = frac{1}{n} sum_{i = 1}^n X_i$. Under the null hypothesis we have $bar{X} sim N(0, 1/n)$ (mean $0$, variance $1/n$). If you say, "I will reject the null hypothesis if $bar{X}$ exceeds threshold $T$" then no matter how large $T$ is (as long as it is finite), we have $P(bar{X} > T) > 0$ and this is our probability of Type I error. If $T = infty$ then you are in the trivial case where your Type I error is $0$ because it is impossible for you to reject the null hypothesis under any circumstances.
Occasionally you can have cases where you can certainly reject the null hypothesis. E.g. if your null hypothesis is that $T$ is an upper bound for observations $X_1, dots, X_n$ and your alternative is that the true upper bound is higher than $T$, then as soon as you observe some $X_i > T$ then you can reject the null hypothesis with no chance of Type I error, since it would be impossible to see $X_i > T$ under the null hypothesis.
The same argument applies for Type II error: if there is any possibility that the data will look like they were generated under the assumptions of the null hypothesis when they are actually generated from the alternative, then you have a non-zero probability of Type II error.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Usually there is no way for the risk of making a Type I error to be $0$. Suppose that you have a test statistic for your null hypothesis and you set a threshold, saying "If the test statistic exceeds this threshold then I will reject the null hypothesis". If there is any possibility that the test statistic will exceed this threshold under the null hypothesis then the Type I error rate will be greater than $0$.
For example, suppose that $X_1, dots, X_n$ are known to be independent and identically distributed random variables with each $X_i sim N(mu, 1)$ (mean $mu$, variance $1$), where the mean is unknown. Let the null hypothesis be that $mu = 0$ and let the alternative be that $mu > 0$. We consider the test statistic $bar{X} = frac{1}{n} sum_{i = 1}^n X_i$. Under the null hypothesis we have $bar{X} sim N(0, 1/n)$ (mean $0$, variance $1/n$). If you say, "I will reject the null hypothesis if $bar{X}$ exceeds threshold $T$" then no matter how large $T$ is (as long as it is finite), we have $P(bar{X} > T) > 0$ and this is our probability of Type I error. If $T = infty$ then you are in the trivial case where your Type I error is $0$ because it is impossible for you to reject the null hypothesis under any circumstances.
Occasionally you can have cases where you can certainly reject the null hypothesis. E.g. if your null hypothesis is that $T$ is an upper bound for observations $X_1, dots, X_n$ and your alternative is that the true upper bound is higher than $T$, then as soon as you observe some $X_i > T$ then you can reject the null hypothesis with no chance of Type I error, since it would be impossible to see $X_i > T$ under the null hypothesis.
The same argument applies for Type II error: if there is any possibility that the data will look like they were generated under the assumptions of the null hypothesis when they are actually generated from the alternative, then you have a non-zero probability of Type II error.
$endgroup$
Usually there is no way for the risk of making a Type I error to be $0$. Suppose that you have a test statistic for your null hypothesis and you set a threshold, saying "If the test statistic exceeds this threshold then I will reject the null hypothesis". If there is any possibility that the test statistic will exceed this threshold under the null hypothesis then the Type I error rate will be greater than $0$.
For example, suppose that $X_1, dots, X_n$ are known to be independent and identically distributed random variables with each $X_i sim N(mu, 1)$ (mean $mu$, variance $1$), where the mean is unknown. Let the null hypothesis be that $mu = 0$ and let the alternative be that $mu > 0$. We consider the test statistic $bar{X} = frac{1}{n} sum_{i = 1}^n X_i$. Under the null hypothesis we have $bar{X} sim N(0, 1/n)$ (mean $0$, variance $1/n$). If you say, "I will reject the null hypothesis if $bar{X}$ exceeds threshold $T$" then no matter how large $T$ is (as long as it is finite), we have $P(bar{X} > T) > 0$ and this is our probability of Type I error. If $T = infty$ then you are in the trivial case where your Type I error is $0$ because it is impossible for you to reject the null hypothesis under any circumstances.
Occasionally you can have cases where you can certainly reject the null hypothesis. E.g. if your null hypothesis is that $T$ is an upper bound for observations $X_1, dots, X_n$ and your alternative is that the true upper bound is higher than $T$, then as soon as you observe some $X_i > T$ then you can reject the null hypothesis with no chance of Type I error, since it would be impossible to see $X_i > T$ under the null hypothesis.
The same argument applies for Type II error: if there is any possibility that the data will look like they were generated under the assumptions of the null hypothesis when they are actually generated from the alternative, then you have a non-zero probability of Type II error.
answered Feb 3 at 11:09
AlexAlex
744412
744412
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
With these triangular distributions, if you set your criterion as shown by the red dashed line, you will never make a mistake by categorizing a member of the blue category as a member of the tan category.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
add a comment |
$begingroup$
With these triangular distributions, if you set your criterion as shown by the red dashed line, you will never make a mistake by categorizing a member of the blue category as a member of the tan category.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
add a comment |
$begingroup$
With these triangular distributions, if you set your criterion as shown by the red dashed line, you will never make a mistake by categorizing a member of the blue category as a member of the tan category.
$endgroup$
With these triangular distributions, if you set your criterion as shown by the red dashed line, you will never make a mistake by categorizing a member of the blue category as a member of the tan category.
answered Jan 30 at 22:01
David G. StorkDavid G. Stork
11.9k41735
11.9k41735
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
Sorry, but I don't see how this answers it, but it gives me belief that is possible.
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 1 at 21:35
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
$begingroup$
With the blue density $P[X>2] = 0$. So if you set the critical value for your test at $x=2$ (or higher) you will never reject $H_0$ when it is true.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 3 at 21:46
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If you want absolutely to avoid type I error in a pregnancy test, always say "you are not pregnant"
Edit: you will find more about the picture and type I and II errors here:
http://www.sethspielman.org/courses/geog5023/r_examples/Type_I_and_II_Errors.html
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If you want absolutely to avoid type I error in a pregnancy test, always say "you are not pregnant"
Edit: you will find more about the picture and type I and II errors here:
http://www.sethspielman.org/courses/geog5023/r_examples/Type_I_and_II_Errors.html
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If you want absolutely to avoid type I error in a pregnancy test, always say "you are not pregnant"
Edit: you will find more about the picture and type I and II errors here:
http://www.sethspielman.org/courses/geog5023/r_examples/Type_I_and_II_Errors.html
$endgroup$
If you want absolutely to avoid type I error in a pregnancy test, always say "you are not pregnant"
Edit: you will find more about the picture and type I and II errors here:
http://www.sethspielman.org/courses/geog5023/r_examples/Type_I_and_II_Errors.html
edited Feb 6 at 8:09
answered Feb 3 at 21:56
BertrandBertrand
45815
45815
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Is this the same as setting the significance level to $0$, right? Also we are reffering to the first pictuare when we say "You are not pregnant"?
$endgroup$
– user625055
Feb 6 at 17:53
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
$begingroup$
Yes, in some examples given here, it is possible to fully eliminate either type I error or type II error. See also the nice example of David G. Stork with triangular densities. Note, however, that it is not "often" possible to fully eliminate type I or II errors (with normal densities having a unbounded support this is not possible). Note also that it is not "often" possible to eliminate both type I and II errors simultaneously. Of course we can built examples for which it is the case, but empirically we have to be cautious and think twice about these issues.
$endgroup$
– Bertrand
Feb 6 at 21:19
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3094161%2fis-it-possible-to-eliminate-completly-the-type-1-error-risk%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
It depends on the problem.
$endgroup$
– David G. Stork
Jan 30 at 21:54