Does the curried version of a bifunctor contain more information?












1












$begingroup$


For functions $f:Xtimes Yto Z$, the curried version $lambda f:Xto (Yto Z)$ is a different way of representing the exact same information.



For functors, I’m assuming that the same should hold, but intuitively I’m thinking that the curried version contains more information.



Consider the similar case for a bifunctor. Given categories $C,D,E$, consider the functor $F:Ctimes Dto E$. We can curry this using the exponential category, and get the functor $lambda F : C to E^D$.



With the base functor $F$, we can EITHER input an object $(c,d)$ OR a morphism $(f,g)$ where $c,d$ are objects and $f,g$ morphisms of $C$ and $D$ respectively. In these two cases we get objects and morphisms in $E$ out of them.



But with the curried functor, we have more options: We can first input an object $c$, and then input an object $d$, which gives us the same as inputting $(c,d)$. We can also input first $c$ and then a morphism $gin D$. Alternatively, we can immediately input a morphism $fin C$ into $lambda F$.



Doesn’t this increased amount of uses of $lambda F$ mean that it has more information than $F$?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$

















    1












    $begingroup$


    For functions $f:Xtimes Yto Z$, the curried version $lambda f:Xto (Yto Z)$ is a different way of representing the exact same information.



    For functors, I’m assuming that the same should hold, but intuitively I’m thinking that the curried version contains more information.



    Consider the similar case for a bifunctor. Given categories $C,D,E$, consider the functor $F:Ctimes Dto E$. We can curry this using the exponential category, and get the functor $lambda F : C to E^D$.



    With the base functor $F$, we can EITHER input an object $(c,d)$ OR a morphism $(f,g)$ where $c,d$ are objects and $f,g$ morphisms of $C$ and $D$ respectively. In these two cases we get objects and morphisms in $E$ out of them.



    But with the curried functor, we have more options: We can first input an object $c$, and then input an object $d$, which gives us the same as inputting $(c,d)$. We can also input first $c$ and then a morphism $gin D$. Alternatively, we can immediately input a morphism $fin C$ into $lambda F$.



    Doesn’t this increased amount of uses of $lambda F$ mean that it has more information than $F$?










    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$















      1












      1








      1





      $begingroup$


      For functions $f:Xtimes Yto Z$, the curried version $lambda f:Xto (Yto Z)$ is a different way of representing the exact same information.



      For functors, I’m assuming that the same should hold, but intuitively I’m thinking that the curried version contains more information.



      Consider the similar case for a bifunctor. Given categories $C,D,E$, consider the functor $F:Ctimes Dto E$. We can curry this using the exponential category, and get the functor $lambda F : C to E^D$.



      With the base functor $F$, we can EITHER input an object $(c,d)$ OR a morphism $(f,g)$ where $c,d$ are objects and $f,g$ morphisms of $C$ and $D$ respectively. In these two cases we get objects and morphisms in $E$ out of them.



      But with the curried functor, we have more options: We can first input an object $c$, and then input an object $d$, which gives us the same as inputting $(c,d)$. We can also input first $c$ and then a morphism $gin D$. Alternatively, we can immediately input a morphism $fin C$ into $lambda F$.



      Doesn’t this increased amount of uses of $lambda F$ mean that it has more information than $F$?










      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      For functions $f:Xtimes Yto Z$, the curried version $lambda f:Xto (Yto Z)$ is a different way of representing the exact same information.



      For functors, I’m assuming that the same should hold, but intuitively I’m thinking that the curried version contains more information.



      Consider the similar case for a bifunctor. Given categories $C,D,E$, consider the functor $F:Ctimes Dto E$. We can curry this using the exponential category, and get the functor $lambda F : C to E^D$.



      With the base functor $F$, we can EITHER input an object $(c,d)$ OR a morphism $(f,g)$ where $c,d$ are objects and $f,g$ morphisms of $C$ and $D$ respectively. In these two cases we get objects and morphisms in $E$ out of them.



      But with the curried functor, we have more options: We can first input an object $c$, and then input an object $d$, which gives us the same as inputting $(c,d)$. We can also input first $c$ and then a morphism $gin D$. Alternatively, we can immediately input a morphism $fin C$ into $lambda F$.



      Doesn’t this increased amount of uses of $lambda F$ mean that it has more information than $F$?







      category-theory






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Jan 30 at 14:15









      user56834user56834

      3,38621253




      3,38621253






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          3












          $begingroup$

          Immediate intuitive answer: it can't, because things ought to be well-behaved, which means that currying ought to be an equivalence of the appropriate categories (in this case: $mathsf{Fun}(C times D, E)$ and $mathsf{Fun}(C, E^D)$) which means it ought to be reversible.



          Let's chase down what happens in the curried version of the functor $lambda F$. If we put in an object $c in C$, this will get sent to what is informally referred to as $F(c, -)$. This functor takes an object $d in D$, and sends it to $F(c, d)$. So what does it do on morphisms? Given $g: d to d'$, we need to get a morphism $F(c, g): F(c, d) to F(c, d')$, and the only reasonable definition is to have $F((mathrm{id}_C, g))$, and you can check that this works. Thus: the information of what happens when you first put an object, and then a morphism, into $lambda F$ is already contained in $F$: you just use the identity morphism of the object.



          For the other direction: if $f: c to c'$ is a morphism, $lambda F(f) = F(f, -)$ ought to be a morphism from $F(c, -) to F(c', -)$. That is, for each $d in D$ we should have a morphism $F(c, d) to F(c', d)$. Again our only real choice is to have this be $F((f, mathrm{id}_D))$. Again, you can check that this works.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:06










          • $begingroup$
            If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:12










          • $begingroup$
            but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:25










          • $begingroup$
            You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:31












          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














          draft saved

          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3093580%2fdoes-the-curried-version-of-a-bifunctor-contain-more-information%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          3












          $begingroup$

          Immediate intuitive answer: it can't, because things ought to be well-behaved, which means that currying ought to be an equivalence of the appropriate categories (in this case: $mathsf{Fun}(C times D, E)$ and $mathsf{Fun}(C, E^D)$) which means it ought to be reversible.



          Let's chase down what happens in the curried version of the functor $lambda F$. If we put in an object $c in C$, this will get sent to what is informally referred to as $F(c, -)$. This functor takes an object $d in D$, and sends it to $F(c, d)$. So what does it do on morphisms? Given $g: d to d'$, we need to get a morphism $F(c, g): F(c, d) to F(c, d')$, and the only reasonable definition is to have $F((mathrm{id}_C, g))$, and you can check that this works. Thus: the information of what happens when you first put an object, and then a morphism, into $lambda F$ is already contained in $F$: you just use the identity morphism of the object.



          For the other direction: if $f: c to c'$ is a morphism, $lambda F(f) = F(f, -)$ ought to be a morphism from $F(c, -) to F(c', -)$. That is, for each $d in D$ we should have a morphism $F(c, d) to F(c', d)$. Again our only real choice is to have this be $F((f, mathrm{id}_D))$. Again, you can check that this works.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:06










          • $begingroup$
            If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:12










          • $begingroup$
            but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:25










          • $begingroup$
            You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:31
















          3












          $begingroup$

          Immediate intuitive answer: it can't, because things ought to be well-behaved, which means that currying ought to be an equivalence of the appropriate categories (in this case: $mathsf{Fun}(C times D, E)$ and $mathsf{Fun}(C, E^D)$) which means it ought to be reversible.



          Let's chase down what happens in the curried version of the functor $lambda F$. If we put in an object $c in C$, this will get sent to what is informally referred to as $F(c, -)$. This functor takes an object $d in D$, and sends it to $F(c, d)$. So what does it do on morphisms? Given $g: d to d'$, we need to get a morphism $F(c, g): F(c, d) to F(c, d')$, and the only reasonable definition is to have $F((mathrm{id}_C, g))$, and you can check that this works. Thus: the information of what happens when you first put an object, and then a morphism, into $lambda F$ is already contained in $F$: you just use the identity morphism of the object.



          For the other direction: if $f: c to c'$ is a morphism, $lambda F(f) = F(f, -)$ ought to be a morphism from $F(c, -) to F(c', -)$. That is, for each $d in D$ we should have a morphism $F(c, d) to F(c', d)$. Again our only real choice is to have this be $F((f, mathrm{id}_D))$. Again, you can check that this works.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:06










          • $begingroup$
            If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:12










          • $begingroup$
            but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:25










          • $begingroup$
            You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:31














          3












          3








          3





          $begingroup$

          Immediate intuitive answer: it can't, because things ought to be well-behaved, which means that currying ought to be an equivalence of the appropriate categories (in this case: $mathsf{Fun}(C times D, E)$ and $mathsf{Fun}(C, E^D)$) which means it ought to be reversible.



          Let's chase down what happens in the curried version of the functor $lambda F$. If we put in an object $c in C$, this will get sent to what is informally referred to as $F(c, -)$. This functor takes an object $d in D$, and sends it to $F(c, d)$. So what does it do on morphisms? Given $g: d to d'$, we need to get a morphism $F(c, g): F(c, d) to F(c, d')$, and the only reasonable definition is to have $F((mathrm{id}_C, g))$, and you can check that this works. Thus: the information of what happens when you first put an object, and then a morphism, into $lambda F$ is already contained in $F$: you just use the identity morphism of the object.



          For the other direction: if $f: c to c'$ is a morphism, $lambda F(f) = F(f, -)$ ought to be a morphism from $F(c, -) to F(c', -)$. That is, for each $d in D$ we should have a morphism $F(c, d) to F(c', d)$. Again our only real choice is to have this be $F((f, mathrm{id}_D))$. Again, you can check that this works.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          Immediate intuitive answer: it can't, because things ought to be well-behaved, which means that currying ought to be an equivalence of the appropriate categories (in this case: $mathsf{Fun}(C times D, E)$ and $mathsf{Fun}(C, E^D)$) which means it ought to be reversible.



          Let's chase down what happens in the curried version of the functor $lambda F$. If we put in an object $c in C$, this will get sent to what is informally referred to as $F(c, -)$. This functor takes an object $d in D$, and sends it to $F(c, d)$. So what does it do on morphisms? Given $g: d to d'$, we need to get a morphism $F(c, g): F(c, d) to F(c, d')$, and the only reasonable definition is to have $F((mathrm{id}_C, g))$, and you can check that this works. Thus: the information of what happens when you first put an object, and then a morphism, into $lambda F$ is already contained in $F$: you just use the identity morphism of the object.



          For the other direction: if $f: c to c'$ is a morphism, $lambda F(f) = F(f, -)$ ought to be a morphism from $F(c, -) to F(c', -)$. That is, for each $d in D$ we should have a morphism $F(c, d) to F(c', d)$. Again our only real choice is to have this be $F((f, mathrm{id}_D))$. Again, you can check that this works.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Jan 30 at 14:35









          Mees de VriesMees de Vries

          17.6k13060




          17.6k13060












          • $begingroup$
            What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:06










          • $begingroup$
            If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:12










          • $begingroup$
            but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:25










          • $begingroup$
            You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:31


















          • $begingroup$
            What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:06










          • $begingroup$
            If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:12










          • $begingroup$
            but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
            $endgroup$
            – user56834
            Feb 4 at 17:25










          • $begingroup$
            You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
            $endgroup$
            – Mees de Vries
            Feb 4 at 17:31
















          $begingroup$
          What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
          $endgroup$
          – user56834
          Feb 4 at 17:06




          $begingroup$
          What still confuses me about the last part is that $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor but a natural transformation (i.e. a morphism in $C$), and so I don't really see why it even makes sense to talk about $lambda F (f) = F(f,-)$. (this is different from the case $lambda F(c)$ where $c$ is an object, because $lambda F(c)$ really is a functor.)
          $endgroup$
          – user56834
          Feb 4 at 17:06












          $begingroup$
          If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
          $endgroup$
          – Mees de Vries
          Feb 4 at 17:12




          $begingroup$
          If you don't like it you can ignore the notation $F(f, -)$ -- it's an abuse of notation that makes it easier for me to keep track of what's happening.
          $endgroup$
          – Mees de Vries
          Feb 4 at 17:12












          $begingroup$
          but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
          $endgroup$
          – user56834
          Feb 4 at 17:25




          $begingroup$
          but even dropping that notation, I am unsure what $lambda F(f)$ is. It is a morphism, and therefore I don’t see how we can “apply” something to it. In other words, I see how we can curry the “object version” of $F$: $F(c,d) = $lambda F(c) (d)$, because $lambda F(c)$ is a functor again. But I can’t see what $lambda F(f) (g)$ even means, because $lambda F(f)$ is not a functor.
          $endgroup$
          – user56834
          Feb 4 at 17:25












          $begingroup$
          You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
          $endgroup$
          – Mees de Vries
          Feb 4 at 17:31




          $begingroup$
          You're right that you cannot "apply" $lambda F(f)$ to something in the same way that you might $lambda F(c)$. The exact way in which the information is encoded in $lambda F$ is different from the way it is encoded in $F$. In particular, $lambda F(f)(d)$ could be an abuse of notation for $lambda F(f)_d : lambda F(c)(d) to lambda F(c')(d)$. And you could abuse your notation further to make $lambda F(f)(g)$, with $g: d to d'$, be equal to either the composition $lambda F(f)(d') circ lambda F(c)(g)$ or $lambda F(c')(g) circ lambda F(f)(d)$ -- naturality says they are equal.
          $endgroup$
          – Mees de Vries
          Feb 4 at 17:31


















          draft saved

          draft discarded




















































          Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3093580%2fdoes-the-curried-version-of-a-bifunctor-contain-more-information%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

          How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

          in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith