Proving that $(omega_n)^omega=omega_n$ providing CH but not GCH
$begingroup$
This is an exercise from a book from Kunen - SET THEORY, An Introduction to Independence Proofs
Assume CH but don't assume GCH. Show that $(omega_n)^omega=omega_n$ for $1 le n < omega$.
I don't have a clue for a good starting point...
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is an exercise from a book from Kunen - SET THEORY, An Introduction to Independence Proofs
Assume CH but don't assume GCH. Show that $(omega_n)^omega=omega_n$ for $1 le n < omega$.
I don't have a clue for a good starting point...
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is an exercise from a book from Kunen - SET THEORY, An Introduction to Independence Proofs
Assume CH but don't assume GCH. Show that $(omega_n)^omega=omega_n$ for $1 le n < omega$.
I don't have a clue for a good starting point...
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
This is an exercise from a book from Kunen - SET THEORY, An Introduction to Independence Proofs
Assume CH but don't assume GCH. Show that $(omega_n)^omega=omega_n$ for $1 le n < omega$.
I don't have a clue for a good starting point...
set-theory cardinals
set-theory cardinals
edited Aug 3 '15 at 14:29
Asaf Karagila♦
308k33441774
308k33441774
asked Aug 3 '15 at 12:54


mathcounterexamples.netmathcounterexamples.net
26.9k22158
26.9k22158
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25
add a comment |
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
HINT: Use Hausdorff's formula which states that $aleph_{alpha+1}^{aleph_beta}=aleph_alpha^{aleph_beta}cdotaleph_{alpha+1}$. And induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Recall that $omega_1$ is a regular cardinal. Now, consider $(omega_1)^omega$ and let $A in (omega_1)^omega$. Define the $sup(A) = alpha$ such that $alpha$ is the smallest ordinal where every $ beta in A$, $ beta < alpha$. Since $cof(omega_1) = omega_1$, we note that $alpha$ must always be a countable ordinal. Partition $ (omega_1)^omega$ into equivalence classes where $A$~ $B$ if $sup(A) = sup(B)$. Denote the equivalence class for some ordinal $alpha$ and $O_alpha$. Notice that $|O_alpha| = 2^{aleph_0} = aleph_1 $ for $omega<alpha <omega_1$ (and $|O_alpha| = emptyset$ for any finite $alpha$).
Thus, $(|omega_1)^omega| = |bigcup_{omega<alpha<omega_1} O_alpha|$. But the RHS is just the $omega_1$ union of sets of size $omega_1$ (which has cardinality $omega_1$).
Now you can finish the problem by induction on $n$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
By CH, we know that $2^omega = omega_1$. Thus, ${omega_1}^omega = (2^omega)^omega = 2^{omegacdotomega} = 2^omega = omega_1$.
Now assume that ${omega_n}^omega = omega_n$. Because $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, any map from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ cannot be cofinal. Thus the set of maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ is the union of the set of maps from $omega$ to $alpha$ where the cardinality of $alpha$ is $omega_n$. By our inductive hypothesis, each element of this union has size $omega_n$ and there are $omega_{n+1}$ members of this union, so the set of all maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ has size no greater than $omega_{n+1}$. Q.E.D.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1382990%2fproving-that-omega-n-omega-omega-n-providing-ch-but-not-gch%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
HINT: Use Hausdorff's formula which states that $aleph_{alpha+1}^{aleph_beta}=aleph_alpha^{aleph_beta}cdotaleph_{alpha+1}$. And induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
HINT: Use Hausdorff's formula which states that $aleph_{alpha+1}^{aleph_beta}=aleph_alpha^{aleph_beta}cdotaleph_{alpha+1}$. And induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
HINT: Use Hausdorff's formula which states that $aleph_{alpha+1}^{aleph_beta}=aleph_alpha^{aleph_beta}cdotaleph_{alpha+1}$. And induction.
$endgroup$
HINT: Use Hausdorff's formula which states that $aleph_{alpha+1}^{aleph_beta}=aleph_alpha^{aleph_beta}cdotaleph_{alpha+1}$. And induction.
answered Aug 3 '15 at 14:28
Asaf Karagila♦Asaf Karagila
308k33441774
308k33441774
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Recall that $omega_1$ is a regular cardinal. Now, consider $(omega_1)^omega$ and let $A in (omega_1)^omega$. Define the $sup(A) = alpha$ such that $alpha$ is the smallest ordinal where every $ beta in A$, $ beta < alpha$. Since $cof(omega_1) = omega_1$, we note that $alpha$ must always be a countable ordinal. Partition $ (omega_1)^omega$ into equivalence classes where $A$~ $B$ if $sup(A) = sup(B)$. Denote the equivalence class for some ordinal $alpha$ and $O_alpha$. Notice that $|O_alpha| = 2^{aleph_0} = aleph_1 $ for $omega<alpha <omega_1$ (and $|O_alpha| = emptyset$ for any finite $alpha$).
Thus, $(|omega_1)^omega| = |bigcup_{omega<alpha<omega_1} O_alpha|$. But the RHS is just the $omega_1$ union of sets of size $omega_1$ (which has cardinality $omega_1$).
Now you can finish the problem by induction on $n$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Recall that $omega_1$ is a regular cardinal. Now, consider $(omega_1)^omega$ and let $A in (omega_1)^omega$. Define the $sup(A) = alpha$ such that $alpha$ is the smallest ordinal where every $ beta in A$, $ beta < alpha$. Since $cof(omega_1) = omega_1$, we note that $alpha$ must always be a countable ordinal. Partition $ (omega_1)^omega$ into equivalence classes where $A$~ $B$ if $sup(A) = sup(B)$. Denote the equivalence class for some ordinal $alpha$ and $O_alpha$. Notice that $|O_alpha| = 2^{aleph_0} = aleph_1 $ for $omega<alpha <omega_1$ (and $|O_alpha| = emptyset$ for any finite $alpha$).
Thus, $(|omega_1)^omega| = |bigcup_{omega<alpha<omega_1} O_alpha|$. But the RHS is just the $omega_1$ union of sets of size $omega_1$ (which has cardinality $omega_1$).
Now you can finish the problem by induction on $n$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Recall that $omega_1$ is a regular cardinal. Now, consider $(omega_1)^omega$ and let $A in (omega_1)^omega$. Define the $sup(A) = alpha$ such that $alpha$ is the smallest ordinal where every $ beta in A$, $ beta < alpha$. Since $cof(omega_1) = omega_1$, we note that $alpha$ must always be a countable ordinal. Partition $ (omega_1)^omega$ into equivalence classes where $A$~ $B$ if $sup(A) = sup(B)$. Denote the equivalence class for some ordinal $alpha$ and $O_alpha$. Notice that $|O_alpha| = 2^{aleph_0} = aleph_1 $ for $omega<alpha <omega_1$ (and $|O_alpha| = emptyset$ for any finite $alpha$).
Thus, $(|omega_1)^omega| = |bigcup_{omega<alpha<omega_1} O_alpha|$. But the RHS is just the $omega_1$ union of sets of size $omega_1$ (which has cardinality $omega_1$).
Now you can finish the problem by induction on $n$.
$endgroup$
Recall that $omega_1$ is a regular cardinal. Now, consider $(omega_1)^omega$ and let $A in (omega_1)^omega$. Define the $sup(A) = alpha$ such that $alpha$ is the smallest ordinal where every $ beta in A$, $ beta < alpha$. Since $cof(omega_1) = omega_1$, we note that $alpha$ must always be a countable ordinal. Partition $ (omega_1)^omega$ into equivalence classes where $A$~ $B$ if $sup(A) = sup(B)$. Denote the equivalence class for some ordinal $alpha$ and $O_alpha$. Notice that $|O_alpha| = 2^{aleph_0} = aleph_1 $ for $omega<alpha <omega_1$ (and $|O_alpha| = emptyset$ for any finite $alpha$).
Thus, $(|omega_1)^omega| = |bigcup_{omega<alpha<omega_1} O_alpha|$. But the RHS is just the $omega_1$ union of sets of size $omega_1$ (which has cardinality $omega_1$).
Now you can finish the problem by induction on $n$.
edited Aug 3 '15 at 13:40
answered Aug 3 '15 at 13:33
KyleKyle
5,29221334
5,29221334
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
By CH, we know that $2^omega = omega_1$. Thus, ${omega_1}^omega = (2^omega)^omega = 2^{omegacdotomega} = 2^omega = omega_1$.
Now assume that ${omega_n}^omega = omega_n$. Because $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, any map from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ cannot be cofinal. Thus the set of maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ is the union of the set of maps from $omega$ to $alpha$ where the cardinality of $alpha$ is $omega_n$. By our inductive hypothesis, each element of this union has size $omega_n$ and there are $omega_{n+1}$ members of this union, so the set of all maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ has size no greater than $omega_{n+1}$. Q.E.D.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
By CH, we know that $2^omega = omega_1$. Thus, ${omega_1}^omega = (2^omega)^omega = 2^{omegacdotomega} = 2^omega = omega_1$.
Now assume that ${omega_n}^omega = omega_n$. Because $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, any map from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ cannot be cofinal. Thus the set of maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ is the union of the set of maps from $omega$ to $alpha$ where the cardinality of $alpha$ is $omega_n$. By our inductive hypothesis, each element of this union has size $omega_n$ and there are $omega_{n+1}$ members of this union, so the set of all maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ has size no greater than $omega_{n+1}$. Q.E.D.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
By CH, we know that $2^omega = omega_1$. Thus, ${omega_1}^omega = (2^omega)^omega = 2^{omegacdotomega} = 2^omega = omega_1$.
Now assume that ${omega_n}^omega = omega_n$. Because $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, any map from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ cannot be cofinal. Thus the set of maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ is the union of the set of maps from $omega$ to $alpha$ where the cardinality of $alpha$ is $omega_n$. By our inductive hypothesis, each element of this union has size $omega_n$ and there are $omega_{n+1}$ members of this union, so the set of all maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ has size no greater than $omega_{n+1}$. Q.E.D.
$endgroup$
By CH, we know that $2^omega = omega_1$. Thus, ${omega_1}^omega = (2^omega)^omega = 2^{omegacdotomega} = 2^omega = omega_1$.
Now assume that ${omega_n}^omega = omega_n$. Because $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, any map from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ cannot be cofinal. Thus the set of maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ is the union of the set of maps from $omega$ to $alpha$ where the cardinality of $alpha$ is $omega_n$. By our inductive hypothesis, each element of this union has size $omega_n$ and there are $omega_{n+1}$ members of this union, so the set of all maps from $omega$ to $omega_{n+1}$ has size no greater than $omega_{n+1}$. Q.E.D.
answered Jan 31 at 2:08
Robert ShoreRobert Shore
3,611324
3,611324
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1382990%2fproving-that-omega-n-omega-omega-n-providing-ch-but-not-gch%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
If you have heard of the Hausdorff formula this follows immediately. If not, a good way to proceed is by induction. The case $n=1$ follows by CH. Now consider $omega_{n+1}^omega$ as the set of functions from $omega$ into $omega_{n+1}$. But $omega_{n+1}$ is regular, so...
$endgroup$
– Miha Habič
Aug 3 '15 at 13:25