What is $aleph_0!$?
What is $aleph_0!$ ?
I know that in the original definition the factorial is defined for natural numbers but, what if we extend this concept to cardinal numbers?
This concept has been extended to the real numbers by the $Gamma$ function but I never see this kind of extension before.
This is a proof that I made by myself and can be incorrect but still interesting for me.
$aleph_0times(aleph_0 - 1)times(aleph_0 - 2)times ...$
We can rewrite this as
$$aleph_0! = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0 - i) = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0)$$
But, is this equal to:
$$aleph_0^{aleph_0}$$
Also, if we assume the continumm hypothesis
$2^{aleph_0} = mathfrak{c} leq aleph_0^{aleph_0} leq mathfrak{c}$
Hence, $aleph_0! = mathfrak{c}$
elementary-set-theory factorial cardinals infinity infinite-product
|
show 4 more comments
What is $aleph_0!$ ?
I know that in the original definition the factorial is defined for natural numbers but, what if we extend this concept to cardinal numbers?
This concept has been extended to the real numbers by the $Gamma$ function but I never see this kind of extension before.
This is a proof that I made by myself and can be incorrect but still interesting for me.
$aleph_0times(aleph_0 - 1)times(aleph_0 - 2)times ...$
We can rewrite this as
$$aleph_0! = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0 - i) = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0)$$
But, is this equal to:
$$aleph_0^{aleph_0}$$
Also, if we assume the continumm hypothesis
$2^{aleph_0} = mathfrak{c} leq aleph_0^{aleph_0} leq mathfrak{c}$
Hence, $aleph_0! = mathfrak{c}$
elementary-set-theory factorial cardinals infinity infinite-product
1
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
1
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
1
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
2
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
1
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28
|
show 4 more comments
What is $aleph_0!$ ?
I know that in the original definition the factorial is defined for natural numbers but, what if we extend this concept to cardinal numbers?
This concept has been extended to the real numbers by the $Gamma$ function but I never see this kind of extension before.
This is a proof that I made by myself and can be incorrect but still interesting for me.
$aleph_0times(aleph_0 - 1)times(aleph_0 - 2)times ...$
We can rewrite this as
$$aleph_0! = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0 - i) = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0)$$
But, is this equal to:
$$aleph_0^{aleph_0}$$
Also, if we assume the continumm hypothesis
$2^{aleph_0} = mathfrak{c} leq aleph_0^{aleph_0} leq mathfrak{c}$
Hence, $aleph_0! = mathfrak{c}$
elementary-set-theory factorial cardinals infinity infinite-product
What is $aleph_0!$ ?
I know that in the original definition the factorial is defined for natural numbers but, what if we extend this concept to cardinal numbers?
This concept has been extended to the real numbers by the $Gamma$ function but I never see this kind of extension before.
This is a proof that I made by myself and can be incorrect but still interesting for me.
$aleph_0times(aleph_0 - 1)times(aleph_0 - 2)times ...$
We can rewrite this as
$$aleph_0! = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0 - i) = prod_{i = 1}^{infty}(aleph_0)$$
But, is this equal to:
$$aleph_0^{aleph_0}$$
Also, if we assume the continumm hypothesis
$2^{aleph_0} = mathfrak{c} leq aleph_0^{aleph_0} leq mathfrak{c}$
Hence, $aleph_0! = mathfrak{c}$
elementary-set-theory factorial cardinals infinity infinite-product
elementary-set-theory factorial cardinals infinity infinite-product
edited Dec 5 '17 at 3:26
Martin Sleziak
44.6k8115271
44.6k8115271
asked Dec 5 '17 at 1:15
Richard ClareRichard Clare
998314
998314
1
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
1
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
1
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
2
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
1
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28
|
show 4 more comments
1
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
1
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
1
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
2
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
1
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28
1
1
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
1
1
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
1
1
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
2
2
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
1
1
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28
|
show 4 more comments
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
First, a couple quick comments:
The continuum hypothesis isn't needed (and I'm not sure how you used it) - $(aleph_0)^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, provably in ZF (we don't even need the axiom of choice!).
Also, subtraction isn't really an appropriate operation on cardinals - while it's clear what $kappa-lambda$ should be if $lambda<kappa$ and $kappa$ is infinite, what is $aleph_0-aleph_0$?
The right definition of the factorial is as the size of the corresponding group of permutations: remember that in the finite case, $n!$ is the number of permutations of an $n$-element set, and this generalizes immediately to the $kappa$-case. It's now not hard to show that $kappa!=kappa^kappa$ in ZFC - that is, there is a bijection between the set of permutations of $kappa$ and the set of all functions from $kappa$ to $kappa$.
And this can be simplified further: it turns out $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$, always. Clearly we have $2^kappalekappa^kappa$, and in the other direction $$kappa^kappale (2^kappa)^kappa=2^{kappacdotkappa}=2^kappa.$$
By the way, the equality $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$ can be proved in ZF alone as long as $kappa$ is well-orderable, the key point being that Cantor-Bernstein doesn't need choice.
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
|
show 5 more comments
You can define the factorial of a cardinal $c$ to be the cardinality of the set of bijections $X to X$ where $X$ is a set with cardinality $c$; this reproduces the usual factorial if $X$ is finite.
So $aleph_0!$ is the cardinality of the set of bijections $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$, and it's not hard to show that this has cardinality $aleph_0^{aleph_0}$, for example using Cantor-Bernstein-Schroder.
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
add a comment |
We have $k!=1cdot2cdots k$, i.e., it is products of all numbers with size at most $k$.
Therefore
$$aleph_0! = 1cdots 2 cdots aleph_0 = prod_{klealeph_0} k$$
seems like a possible generalization. (Although probably taking the number of bijections - as suggested in other answers - is a more natural generalization.)
I will add that the above product has two - it can be reformulated in this way: For each $klealeph_0$ we have a set $A_k$ such that $|A_k|=k$. And we are interested in the cardinality of the Cartesian product of these sets $prod_{klealpha_0} A_k$.
It is not difficult to see that if we use this definition, then
$$2^{aleph_0} le aleph_0! le aleph_0^{aleph_0}.$$
Together with $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, we get $aleph_0! = 2^{aleph_0}$.
If we wanted to do similar generalization for higher cardinalities, we could define
$$kappa! = prod_{alphalekappa} |alpha|$$
where the product is taken over all ordinals $lekappa$. Then exactly the same argument shows that $2^kappa le kappa! le kappa^kappa$.
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2551471%2fwhat-is-aleph-0%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
First, a couple quick comments:
The continuum hypothesis isn't needed (and I'm not sure how you used it) - $(aleph_0)^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, provably in ZF (we don't even need the axiom of choice!).
Also, subtraction isn't really an appropriate operation on cardinals - while it's clear what $kappa-lambda$ should be if $lambda<kappa$ and $kappa$ is infinite, what is $aleph_0-aleph_0$?
The right definition of the factorial is as the size of the corresponding group of permutations: remember that in the finite case, $n!$ is the number of permutations of an $n$-element set, and this generalizes immediately to the $kappa$-case. It's now not hard to show that $kappa!=kappa^kappa$ in ZFC - that is, there is a bijection between the set of permutations of $kappa$ and the set of all functions from $kappa$ to $kappa$.
And this can be simplified further: it turns out $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$, always. Clearly we have $2^kappalekappa^kappa$, and in the other direction $$kappa^kappale (2^kappa)^kappa=2^{kappacdotkappa}=2^kappa.$$
By the way, the equality $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$ can be proved in ZF alone as long as $kappa$ is well-orderable, the key point being that Cantor-Bernstein doesn't need choice.
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
|
show 5 more comments
First, a couple quick comments:
The continuum hypothesis isn't needed (and I'm not sure how you used it) - $(aleph_0)^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, provably in ZF (we don't even need the axiom of choice!).
Also, subtraction isn't really an appropriate operation on cardinals - while it's clear what $kappa-lambda$ should be if $lambda<kappa$ and $kappa$ is infinite, what is $aleph_0-aleph_0$?
The right definition of the factorial is as the size of the corresponding group of permutations: remember that in the finite case, $n!$ is the number of permutations of an $n$-element set, and this generalizes immediately to the $kappa$-case. It's now not hard to show that $kappa!=kappa^kappa$ in ZFC - that is, there is a bijection between the set of permutations of $kappa$ and the set of all functions from $kappa$ to $kappa$.
And this can be simplified further: it turns out $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$, always. Clearly we have $2^kappalekappa^kappa$, and in the other direction $$kappa^kappale (2^kappa)^kappa=2^{kappacdotkappa}=2^kappa.$$
By the way, the equality $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$ can be proved in ZF alone as long as $kappa$ is well-orderable, the key point being that Cantor-Bernstein doesn't need choice.
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
|
show 5 more comments
First, a couple quick comments:
The continuum hypothesis isn't needed (and I'm not sure how you used it) - $(aleph_0)^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, provably in ZF (we don't even need the axiom of choice!).
Also, subtraction isn't really an appropriate operation on cardinals - while it's clear what $kappa-lambda$ should be if $lambda<kappa$ and $kappa$ is infinite, what is $aleph_0-aleph_0$?
The right definition of the factorial is as the size of the corresponding group of permutations: remember that in the finite case, $n!$ is the number of permutations of an $n$-element set, and this generalizes immediately to the $kappa$-case. It's now not hard to show that $kappa!=kappa^kappa$ in ZFC - that is, there is a bijection between the set of permutations of $kappa$ and the set of all functions from $kappa$ to $kappa$.
And this can be simplified further: it turns out $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$, always. Clearly we have $2^kappalekappa^kappa$, and in the other direction $$kappa^kappale (2^kappa)^kappa=2^{kappacdotkappa}=2^kappa.$$
By the way, the equality $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$ can be proved in ZF alone as long as $kappa$ is well-orderable, the key point being that Cantor-Bernstein doesn't need choice.
First, a couple quick comments:
The continuum hypothesis isn't needed (and I'm not sure how you used it) - $(aleph_0)^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, provably in ZF (we don't even need the axiom of choice!).
Also, subtraction isn't really an appropriate operation on cardinals - while it's clear what $kappa-lambda$ should be if $lambda<kappa$ and $kappa$ is infinite, what is $aleph_0-aleph_0$?
The right definition of the factorial is as the size of the corresponding group of permutations: remember that in the finite case, $n!$ is the number of permutations of an $n$-element set, and this generalizes immediately to the $kappa$-case. It's now not hard to show that $kappa!=kappa^kappa$ in ZFC - that is, there is a bijection between the set of permutations of $kappa$ and the set of all functions from $kappa$ to $kappa$.
And this can be simplified further: it turns out $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$, always. Clearly we have $2^kappalekappa^kappa$, and in the other direction $$kappa^kappale (2^kappa)^kappa=2^{kappacdotkappa}=2^kappa.$$
By the way, the equality $kappa^kappa=2^kappa$ can be proved in ZF alone as long as $kappa$ is well-orderable, the key point being that Cantor-Bernstein doesn't need choice.
edited Dec 5 '17 at 3:47
answered Dec 5 '17 at 1:30
Noah SchweberNoah Schweber
122k10149284
122k10149284
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
|
show 5 more comments
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
Can we say that $aleph_0 - aleph_0 = 0$ ? and $0! = 1$ ?
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
By the way great answer.
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 1:37
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
@RichardClare But why is $0$ privileged there? After all, $aleph_0+17=aleph_0$, so shouldn't $aleph_0-aleph_0=17$?
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:07
2
2
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
For comparison, I will add a link to with Andreas Blass' answer to: Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set: "John Dawson and Paul Howard have shown that, in choiceless set theory, the number of permutations of an infinite set $X$ can consistently be related to the number of subsets of $X$ by a strict inequality in either direction; the two numbers can also be incomparable; and of course they can be equal as in the presence of choice. (Slogan: Without choice, nothing can be proved about those two cardinals.)"
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:51
1
1
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
I suppose that the only use of axiom of choice in the above is to get $kappacdotkappa=kappa$ (or $|Xtimes X|=|X|$). But we can still prove that the number of permutations is $kappa^kappa$ for $|X|=kappa$ even in ZF.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:52
|
show 5 more comments
You can define the factorial of a cardinal $c$ to be the cardinality of the set of bijections $X to X$ where $X$ is a set with cardinality $c$; this reproduces the usual factorial if $X$ is finite.
So $aleph_0!$ is the cardinality of the set of bijections $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$, and it's not hard to show that this has cardinality $aleph_0^{aleph_0}$, for example using Cantor-Bernstein-Schroder.
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
add a comment |
You can define the factorial of a cardinal $c$ to be the cardinality of the set of bijections $X to X$ where $X$ is a set with cardinality $c$; this reproduces the usual factorial if $X$ is finite.
So $aleph_0!$ is the cardinality of the set of bijections $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$, and it's not hard to show that this has cardinality $aleph_0^{aleph_0}$, for example using Cantor-Bernstein-Schroder.
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
add a comment |
You can define the factorial of a cardinal $c$ to be the cardinality of the set of bijections $X to X$ where $X$ is a set with cardinality $c$; this reproduces the usual factorial if $X$ is finite.
So $aleph_0!$ is the cardinality of the set of bijections $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$, and it's not hard to show that this has cardinality $aleph_0^{aleph_0}$, for example using Cantor-Bernstein-Schroder.
You can define the factorial of a cardinal $c$ to be the cardinality of the set of bijections $X to X$ where $X$ is a set with cardinality $c$; this reproduces the usual factorial if $X$ is finite.
So $aleph_0!$ is the cardinality of the set of bijections $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$, and it's not hard to show that this has cardinality $aleph_0^{aleph_0}$, for example using Cantor-Bernstein-Schroder.
answered Dec 5 '17 at 1:29
Qiaochu YuanQiaochu Yuan
277k32583919
277k32583919
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
add a comment |
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
And note that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$.
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 1:31
1
1
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@Noah: Is that for Real ?
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 1:36
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
@GeorgesElencwajg Yes? Any function $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{N}$ can be coded as its graph $S_f={langle x, yrangle: f(x)=y}$ (where $langlecdot,cdotrangle$ is your favorite pairing function on $mathbb{N}$); the map $fmapsto S_f$ is an injection. (And in my answer I show - well okay, there are steps to fill in - that $2^kappa=kappa^kappa$ is true for all infinite $kappa$.)
– Noah Schweber
Dec 5 '17 at 2:05
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
Some other posts about cardinality of all bijections $mathbb Ntomathbb N$: Cardinality of the set of bijective functions on $mathbb{N}$?, Problems about Countability related to Function Spaces and also (on MathOverflow) An easy proof of the uncountability of bijections on natural numbers?. For $Xto X$, there is Cardinality of the permutations of an infinite set on MO.
– Martin Sleziak
Dec 5 '17 at 2:38
3
3
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
Dear @ Noah: sorry, I was just making a sophomoric pun on the fact that $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$ is the cardinality of the Reals. But of course I never doubted the correctness of your mathematics :-)
– Georges Elencwajg
Dec 5 '17 at 9:59
add a comment |
We have $k!=1cdot2cdots k$, i.e., it is products of all numbers with size at most $k$.
Therefore
$$aleph_0! = 1cdots 2 cdots aleph_0 = prod_{klealeph_0} k$$
seems like a possible generalization. (Although probably taking the number of bijections - as suggested in other answers - is a more natural generalization.)
I will add that the above product has two - it can be reformulated in this way: For each $klealeph_0$ we have a set $A_k$ such that $|A_k|=k$. And we are interested in the cardinality of the Cartesian product of these sets $prod_{klealpha_0} A_k$.
It is not difficult to see that if we use this definition, then
$$2^{aleph_0} le aleph_0! le aleph_0^{aleph_0}.$$
Together with $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, we get $aleph_0! = 2^{aleph_0}$.
If we wanted to do similar generalization for higher cardinalities, we could define
$$kappa! = prod_{alphalekappa} |alpha|$$
where the product is taken over all ordinals $lekappa$. Then exactly the same argument shows that $2^kappa le kappa! le kappa^kappa$.
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
add a comment |
We have $k!=1cdot2cdots k$, i.e., it is products of all numbers with size at most $k$.
Therefore
$$aleph_0! = 1cdots 2 cdots aleph_0 = prod_{klealeph_0} k$$
seems like a possible generalization. (Although probably taking the number of bijections - as suggested in other answers - is a more natural generalization.)
I will add that the above product has two - it can be reformulated in this way: For each $klealeph_0$ we have a set $A_k$ such that $|A_k|=k$. And we are interested in the cardinality of the Cartesian product of these sets $prod_{klealpha_0} A_k$.
It is not difficult to see that if we use this definition, then
$$2^{aleph_0} le aleph_0! le aleph_0^{aleph_0}.$$
Together with $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, we get $aleph_0! = 2^{aleph_0}$.
If we wanted to do similar generalization for higher cardinalities, we could define
$$kappa! = prod_{alphalekappa} |alpha|$$
where the product is taken over all ordinals $lekappa$. Then exactly the same argument shows that $2^kappa le kappa! le kappa^kappa$.
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
add a comment |
We have $k!=1cdot2cdots k$, i.e., it is products of all numbers with size at most $k$.
Therefore
$$aleph_0! = 1cdots 2 cdots aleph_0 = prod_{klealeph_0} k$$
seems like a possible generalization. (Although probably taking the number of bijections - as suggested in other answers - is a more natural generalization.)
I will add that the above product has two - it can be reformulated in this way: For each $klealeph_0$ we have a set $A_k$ such that $|A_k|=k$. And we are interested in the cardinality of the Cartesian product of these sets $prod_{klealpha_0} A_k$.
It is not difficult to see that if we use this definition, then
$$2^{aleph_0} le aleph_0! le aleph_0^{aleph_0}.$$
Together with $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, we get $aleph_0! = 2^{aleph_0}$.
If we wanted to do similar generalization for higher cardinalities, we could define
$$kappa! = prod_{alphalekappa} |alpha|$$
where the product is taken over all ordinals $lekappa$. Then exactly the same argument shows that $2^kappa le kappa! le kappa^kappa$.
We have $k!=1cdot2cdots k$, i.e., it is products of all numbers with size at most $k$.
Therefore
$$aleph_0! = 1cdots 2 cdots aleph_0 = prod_{klealeph_0} k$$
seems like a possible generalization. (Although probably taking the number of bijections - as suggested in other answers - is a more natural generalization.)
I will add that the above product has two - it can be reformulated in this way: For each $klealeph_0$ we have a set $A_k$ such that $|A_k|=k$. And we are interested in the cardinality of the Cartesian product of these sets $prod_{klealpha_0} A_k$.
It is not difficult to see that if we use this definition, then
$$2^{aleph_0} le aleph_0! le aleph_0^{aleph_0}.$$
Together with $aleph_0^{aleph_0}=2^{aleph_0}$, we get $aleph_0! = 2^{aleph_0}$.
If we wanted to do similar generalization for higher cardinalities, we could define
$$kappa! = prod_{alphalekappa} |alpha|$$
where the product is taken over all ordinals $lekappa$. Then exactly the same argument shows that $2^kappa le kappa! le kappa^kappa$.
edited Dec 5 '17 at 3:29
answered Dec 5 '17 at 3:04
Martin SleziakMartin Sleziak
44.6k8115271
44.6k8115271
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
add a comment |
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
I love your approach. Thanks!
– Richard Clare
Dec 5 '17 at 3:42
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2551471%2fwhat-is-aleph-0%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
I am not sure that factorials are defined on infinite cardinals. Are you using a definition that says otherwise?
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:17
1
Ah, I see. Actually you have other types of extensions, like the $Gamma$ function.
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
1
Hey, great minds think alike ;).
– gary
Dec 5 '17 at 1:20
2
I believe you are for the most part correc with your result. Not sure about the proof. The answer can be found here: math.stackexchange.com/questions/807730/…
– Dair
Dec 5 '17 at 1:22
1
You could also define it to be the number of bijections from $A$ to $A$ where $A$ is any countably infinite set. Then for $A = mathbb{N}$, it's clearly $le aleph_0^{aleph_0}$; and since you can construct $2^{aleph_0}$ bijections by choosing whether to transpose 1 and 2 or leave them fixed, then the same for 3 and 4, ..., $2n+1$ and $2n+2$, ..., that determines what the number of bijections is.
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 5 '17 at 1:28