Why don't we use closed covers to define compactness of metric space?












9












$begingroup$


I'm a beginner in metric space. So many books I've read, there is only the notion of open covers. I want to know why do we worry about open covers to define the compactness of metric spaces and why don't we use closed covers? What is the problem in defining closed cover of a set? Can we use the alternative definition of compactness: "Every closed cover has a finite subcover"?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 8




    $begingroup$
    No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:19






  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 2 at 15:23








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:24






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
    $endgroup$
    – Dog_69
    Feb 2 at 17:19






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Feb 2 at 21:34
















9












$begingroup$


I'm a beginner in metric space. So many books I've read, there is only the notion of open covers. I want to know why do we worry about open covers to define the compactness of metric spaces and why don't we use closed covers? What is the problem in defining closed cover of a set? Can we use the alternative definition of compactness: "Every closed cover has a finite subcover"?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 8




    $begingroup$
    No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:19






  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 2 at 15:23








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:24






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
    $endgroup$
    – Dog_69
    Feb 2 at 17:19






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Feb 2 at 21:34














9












9








9


6



$begingroup$


I'm a beginner in metric space. So many books I've read, there is only the notion of open covers. I want to know why do we worry about open covers to define the compactness of metric spaces and why don't we use closed covers? What is the problem in defining closed cover of a set? Can we use the alternative definition of compactness: "Every closed cover has a finite subcover"?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I'm a beginner in metric space. So many books I've read, there is only the notion of open covers. I want to know why do we worry about open covers to define the compactness of metric spaces and why don't we use closed covers? What is the problem in defining closed cover of a set? Can we use the alternative definition of compactness: "Every closed cover has a finite subcover"?







real-analysis general-topology metric-spaces compactness






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Feb 2 at 23:16









peterh

2,20851731




2,20851731










asked Feb 2 at 15:16









Arjun BanerjeeArjun Banerjee

568110




568110








  • 8




    $begingroup$
    No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:19






  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 2 at 15:23








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:24






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
    $endgroup$
    – Dog_69
    Feb 2 at 17:19






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Feb 2 at 21:34














  • 8




    $begingroup$
    No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:19






  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 2 at 15:23








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
    $endgroup$
    – Alessandro Codenotti
    Feb 2 at 15:24






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
    $endgroup$
    – Dog_69
    Feb 2 at 17:19






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Feb 2 at 21:34








8




8




$begingroup$
No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Feb 2 at 15:19




$begingroup$
No infinite $T_1$ space would be compact: cover it by singletons
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Feb 2 at 15:19




4




4




$begingroup$
Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Feb 2 at 15:23






$begingroup$
Because then the only "compact" metric spaces are the finite ones. No new info.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Feb 2 at 15:23






3




3




$begingroup$
Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Feb 2 at 15:24




$begingroup$
Because definitions are supposed to be useful and a definition of compact in which almost no space is compact wouldn't be. The definition by open sets happens to be the correct one, but I don't know if there is any better explanation than "it works"
$endgroup$
– Alessandro Codenotti
Feb 2 at 15:24




3




3




$begingroup$
I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
$endgroup$
– Dog_69
Feb 2 at 17:19




$begingroup$
I think the question is quite interesting. Topology is always based on open sets, but an equivalent definition of topology can be stated using closed sets. And it seems here we can do too. To every open covering one can associated a closed covering just by taking complements. And if the space is compact, there exists a finite open subcovering and thus a finite closed covering. So, in my opinion, the question is not as easy to answer as it may suggest in some comments. On the other hand, answering a question simply by saying "it works" doesn't seem to be very clever.
$endgroup$
– Dog_69
Feb 2 at 17:19




3




3




$begingroup$
@Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
$endgroup$
– timtfj
Feb 2 at 21:34




$begingroup$
@Dog_69 I mean responses, usually in comnents, that give a trivial or non-explanatory answer to a good question—like "that's just how it is" or whatever—instead of helping the questioner understand anything. "Why" questions seem especially prone to this, because there's usually a trivial reason as well as the deeper one that's being asked for.
$endgroup$
– timtfj
Feb 2 at 21:34










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















31












$begingroup$

It is important to understand that, although definitions often look arbitrary, they never are. Mathematical objects are intended to model something, and you can't understand why the definition is the way it is until you understand what it is trying to model. The question you asked is exactly the right one: why is it defined this way and not some other way? What is it trying to model?



(For example, why does a topology say that arbitrary unions of open sets are open, but infinite intersections of open sets might not be? It's because topology is intended to be an abstraction of certain properties of the line and the plane, and open sets are intended to be a more general version of open intervals of the line and open discs in plane, and that is how the intervals and discs behave.)



This case is similar. Mathematicians noticed that there are certain sorts of “well-behaved” subsets of the line and of metric spaces in general. For example:




  1. A continuous function is always uniformly continuous — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  2. A continuous real-valued function is always bounded — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  3. If $f$ is a continuous real-valued function on some domain, there may be some $m$ at which $f$ is maximized: $f(x) ≤ f(m)$ for all $x$. This is true of all such $f$ if and only if the domain is well-behaved in this way

  4. Every sequence of points from a subset of $Bbb R^n$ contains a convergent subsequence — if and only if the subset is well-behaved in this way


and so on. It took mathematicians quite a long time to understand this properly, but the answer turned out to be that the "well-behaved" property is compactness. There are several equivalent formulations of it, including the open cover formulation you mentioned.



In contrast, the alternative property you propose, with closed covers, turns out not to model anything interesting, and actually to be trivial, as the comments point out. It ends nowhere. But even if it ended somewhere nontrivial, it would be a curiosity, of not much interest, unless it had started from a desire to better understand of something we already wanted to understand. It's quite easy to make up new mathematical properties at random, and to prove theorems about those properties, and sometimes it might seem like that is what we are doing. But we never are.



Properly formulated, compactness turns out to be surprisingly deep. Before compactness, mathematics already had an idea of what a finite set was. Finite sets are always discrete, but not all discrete sets are finite.

Compactness is the missing ingredient: a finite set is one that is both discrete and compact. With the discovery of compactness, we were able to understand finiteness as a conjunction of two properties that are more fundamental! Some of the properties we associate with finiteness actually come from discreteness; others come from compactness. (Some come from both.) Isn't that interesting?



And formulating compactness correctly helps us better understand the original space, $Bbb R^n$ and metric spaces in general. Once we get compactness right, we see that the properties of "well-behaved" sets I mentioned above are not true of all compact spaces; metric spaces are special in several ways, which we didn't formerly appreciate.



Keep asking these questions. Every definition is made for a reason.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 3




    $begingroup$
    To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    Feb 2 at 18:44






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
    $endgroup$
    – user159517
    Feb 2 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
    $endgroup$
    – MJD
    Feb 2 at 21:06






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
    $endgroup$
    – Owen
    Feb 2 at 21:46












Your Answer








StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3097385%2fwhy-dont-we-use-closed-covers-to-define-compactness-of-metric-space%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









31












$begingroup$

It is important to understand that, although definitions often look arbitrary, they never are. Mathematical objects are intended to model something, and you can't understand why the definition is the way it is until you understand what it is trying to model. The question you asked is exactly the right one: why is it defined this way and not some other way? What is it trying to model?



(For example, why does a topology say that arbitrary unions of open sets are open, but infinite intersections of open sets might not be? It's because topology is intended to be an abstraction of certain properties of the line and the plane, and open sets are intended to be a more general version of open intervals of the line and open discs in plane, and that is how the intervals and discs behave.)



This case is similar. Mathematicians noticed that there are certain sorts of “well-behaved” subsets of the line and of metric spaces in general. For example:




  1. A continuous function is always uniformly continuous — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  2. A continuous real-valued function is always bounded — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  3. If $f$ is a continuous real-valued function on some domain, there may be some $m$ at which $f$ is maximized: $f(x) ≤ f(m)$ for all $x$. This is true of all such $f$ if and only if the domain is well-behaved in this way

  4. Every sequence of points from a subset of $Bbb R^n$ contains a convergent subsequence — if and only if the subset is well-behaved in this way


and so on. It took mathematicians quite a long time to understand this properly, but the answer turned out to be that the "well-behaved" property is compactness. There are several equivalent formulations of it, including the open cover formulation you mentioned.



In contrast, the alternative property you propose, with closed covers, turns out not to model anything interesting, and actually to be trivial, as the comments point out. It ends nowhere. But even if it ended somewhere nontrivial, it would be a curiosity, of not much interest, unless it had started from a desire to better understand of something we already wanted to understand. It's quite easy to make up new mathematical properties at random, and to prove theorems about those properties, and sometimes it might seem like that is what we are doing. But we never are.



Properly formulated, compactness turns out to be surprisingly deep. Before compactness, mathematics already had an idea of what a finite set was. Finite sets are always discrete, but not all discrete sets are finite.

Compactness is the missing ingredient: a finite set is one that is both discrete and compact. With the discovery of compactness, we were able to understand finiteness as a conjunction of two properties that are more fundamental! Some of the properties we associate with finiteness actually come from discreteness; others come from compactness. (Some come from both.) Isn't that interesting?



And formulating compactness correctly helps us better understand the original space, $Bbb R^n$ and metric spaces in general. Once we get compactness right, we see that the properties of "well-behaved" sets I mentioned above are not true of all compact spaces; metric spaces are special in several ways, which we didn't formerly appreciate.



Keep asking these questions. Every definition is made for a reason.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 3




    $begingroup$
    To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    Feb 2 at 18:44






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
    $endgroup$
    – user159517
    Feb 2 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
    $endgroup$
    – MJD
    Feb 2 at 21:06






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
    $endgroup$
    – Owen
    Feb 2 at 21:46
















31












$begingroup$

It is important to understand that, although definitions often look arbitrary, they never are. Mathematical objects are intended to model something, and you can't understand why the definition is the way it is until you understand what it is trying to model. The question you asked is exactly the right one: why is it defined this way and not some other way? What is it trying to model?



(For example, why does a topology say that arbitrary unions of open sets are open, but infinite intersections of open sets might not be? It's because topology is intended to be an abstraction of certain properties of the line and the plane, and open sets are intended to be a more general version of open intervals of the line and open discs in plane, and that is how the intervals and discs behave.)



This case is similar. Mathematicians noticed that there are certain sorts of “well-behaved” subsets of the line and of metric spaces in general. For example:




  1. A continuous function is always uniformly continuous — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  2. A continuous real-valued function is always bounded — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  3. If $f$ is a continuous real-valued function on some domain, there may be some $m$ at which $f$ is maximized: $f(x) ≤ f(m)$ for all $x$. This is true of all such $f$ if and only if the domain is well-behaved in this way

  4. Every sequence of points from a subset of $Bbb R^n$ contains a convergent subsequence — if and only if the subset is well-behaved in this way


and so on. It took mathematicians quite a long time to understand this properly, but the answer turned out to be that the "well-behaved" property is compactness. There are several equivalent formulations of it, including the open cover formulation you mentioned.



In contrast, the alternative property you propose, with closed covers, turns out not to model anything interesting, and actually to be trivial, as the comments point out. It ends nowhere. But even if it ended somewhere nontrivial, it would be a curiosity, of not much interest, unless it had started from a desire to better understand of something we already wanted to understand. It's quite easy to make up new mathematical properties at random, and to prove theorems about those properties, and sometimes it might seem like that is what we are doing. But we never are.



Properly formulated, compactness turns out to be surprisingly deep. Before compactness, mathematics already had an idea of what a finite set was. Finite sets are always discrete, but not all discrete sets are finite.

Compactness is the missing ingredient: a finite set is one that is both discrete and compact. With the discovery of compactness, we were able to understand finiteness as a conjunction of two properties that are more fundamental! Some of the properties we associate with finiteness actually come from discreteness; others come from compactness. (Some come from both.) Isn't that interesting?



And formulating compactness correctly helps us better understand the original space, $Bbb R^n$ and metric spaces in general. Once we get compactness right, we see that the properties of "well-behaved" sets I mentioned above are not true of all compact spaces; metric spaces are special in several ways, which we didn't formerly appreciate.



Keep asking these questions. Every definition is made for a reason.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$









  • 3




    $begingroup$
    To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    Feb 2 at 18:44






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
    $endgroup$
    – user159517
    Feb 2 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
    $endgroup$
    – MJD
    Feb 2 at 21:06






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
    $endgroup$
    – Owen
    Feb 2 at 21:46














31












31








31





$begingroup$

It is important to understand that, although definitions often look arbitrary, they never are. Mathematical objects are intended to model something, and you can't understand why the definition is the way it is until you understand what it is trying to model. The question you asked is exactly the right one: why is it defined this way and not some other way? What is it trying to model?



(For example, why does a topology say that arbitrary unions of open sets are open, but infinite intersections of open sets might not be? It's because topology is intended to be an abstraction of certain properties of the line and the plane, and open sets are intended to be a more general version of open intervals of the line and open discs in plane, and that is how the intervals and discs behave.)



This case is similar. Mathematicians noticed that there are certain sorts of “well-behaved” subsets of the line and of metric spaces in general. For example:




  1. A continuous function is always uniformly continuous — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  2. A continuous real-valued function is always bounded — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  3. If $f$ is a continuous real-valued function on some domain, there may be some $m$ at which $f$ is maximized: $f(x) ≤ f(m)$ for all $x$. This is true of all such $f$ if and only if the domain is well-behaved in this way

  4. Every sequence of points from a subset of $Bbb R^n$ contains a convergent subsequence — if and only if the subset is well-behaved in this way


and so on. It took mathematicians quite a long time to understand this properly, but the answer turned out to be that the "well-behaved" property is compactness. There are several equivalent formulations of it, including the open cover formulation you mentioned.



In contrast, the alternative property you propose, with closed covers, turns out not to model anything interesting, and actually to be trivial, as the comments point out. It ends nowhere. But even if it ended somewhere nontrivial, it would be a curiosity, of not much interest, unless it had started from a desire to better understand of something we already wanted to understand. It's quite easy to make up new mathematical properties at random, and to prove theorems about those properties, and sometimes it might seem like that is what we are doing. But we never are.



Properly formulated, compactness turns out to be surprisingly deep. Before compactness, mathematics already had an idea of what a finite set was. Finite sets are always discrete, but not all discrete sets are finite.

Compactness is the missing ingredient: a finite set is one that is both discrete and compact. With the discovery of compactness, we were able to understand finiteness as a conjunction of two properties that are more fundamental! Some of the properties we associate with finiteness actually come from discreteness; others come from compactness. (Some come from both.) Isn't that interesting?



And formulating compactness correctly helps us better understand the original space, $Bbb R^n$ and metric spaces in general. Once we get compactness right, we see that the properties of "well-behaved" sets I mentioned above are not true of all compact spaces; metric spaces are special in several ways, which we didn't formerly appreciate.



Keep asking these questions. Every definition is made for a reason.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



It is important to understand that, although definitions often look arbitrary, they never are. Mathematical objects are intended to model something, and you can't understand why the definition is the way it is until you understand what it is trying to model. The question you asked is exactly the right one: why is it defined this way and not some other way? What is it trying to model?



(For example, why does a topology say that arbitrary unions of open sets are open, but infinite intersections of open sets might not be? It's because topology is intended to be an abstraction of certain properties of the line and the plane, and open sets are intended to be a more general version of open intervals of the line and open discs in plane, and that is how the intervals and discs behave.)



This case is similar. Mathematicians noticed that there are certain sorts of “well-behaved” subsets of the line and of metric spaces in general. For example:




  1. A continuous function is always uniformly continuous — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  2. A continuous real-valued function is always bounded — if and only if its domain is well-behaved in this way

  3. If $f$ is a continuous real-valued function on some domain, there may be some $m$ at which $f$ is maximized: $f(x) ≤ f(m)$ for all $x$. This is true of all such $f$ if and only if the domain is well-behaved in this way

  4. Every sequence of points from a subset of $Bbb R^n$ contains a convergent subsequence — if and only if the subset is well-behaved in this way


and so on. It took mathematicians quite a long time to understand this properly, but the answer turned out to be that the "well-behaved" property is compactness. There are several equivalent formulations of it, including the open cover formulation you mentioned.



In contrast, the alternative property you propose, with closed covers, turns out not to model anything interesting, and actually to be trivial, as the comments point out. It ends nowhere. But even if it ended somewhere nontrivial, it would be a curiosity, of not much interest, unless it had started from a desire to better understand of something we already wanted to understand. It's quite easy to make up new mathematical properties at random, and to prove theorems about those properties, and sometimes it might seem like that is what we are doing. But we never are.



Properly formulated, compactness turns out to be surprisingly deep. Before compactness, mathematics already had an idea of what a finite set was. Finite sets are always discrete, but not all discrete sets are finite.

Compactness is the missing ingredient: a finite set is one that is both discrete and compact. With the discovery of compactness, we were able to understand finiteness as a conjunction of two properties that are more fundamental! Some of the properties we associate with finiteness actually come from discreteness; others come from compactness. (Some come from both.) Isn't that interesting?



And formulating compactness correctly helps us better understand the original space, $Bbb R^n$ and metric spaces in general. Once we get compactness right, we see that the properties of "well-behaved" sets I mentioned above are not true of all compact spaces; metric spaces are special in several ways, which we didn't formerly appreciate.



Keep asking these questions. Every definition is made for a reason.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Feb 2 at 21:05


























community wiki





4 revs
MJD









  • 3




    $begingroup$
    To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    Feb 2 at 18:44






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
    $endgroup$
    – user159517
    Feb 2 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
    $endgroup$
    – MJD
    Feb 2 at 21:06






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
    $endgroup$
    – Owen
    Feb 2 at 21:46














  • 3




    $begingroup$
    To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    Feb 2 at 18:44






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
    $endgroup$
    – user159517
    Feb 2 at 19:41










  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
    $endgroup$
    – MJD
    Feb 2 at 21:06






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
    $endgroup$
    – Owen
    Feb 2 at 21:46








3




3




$begingroup$
To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
$endgroup$
– Hagen von Eitzen
Feb 2 at 18:44




$begingroup$
To add to the last sentence: And it is always a worthwhile exercise to learn about that reason by playing with definitions as the OP did here (replace open with closed cover) or e.g. swapping the quantors in the $epsilondelta$ definition of continuity or or or ... and see how that breaks the nice properties the concept given by original definition has
$endgroup$
– Hagen von Eitzen
Feb 2 at 18:44




1




1




$begingroup$
As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
$endgroup$
– user159517
Feb 2 at 19:41




$begingroup$
As I read it, the "only if" in 3 is not true - any constant function $f$ is a counterexample.
$endgroup$
– user159517
Feb 2 at 19:41












$begingroup$
Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Feb 2 at 21:06




$begingroup$
Thanks. I have corrected the statement of (3) to make the quantifiers clearer.
$endgroup$
– MJD
Feb 2 at 21:06




1




1




$begingroup$
@MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
$endgroup$
– Owen
Feb 2 at 21:46




$begingroup$
@MJD the same issue of the quantifiers would apply to (1) and (2), I believe (though I think it's clear what you mean).
$endgroup$
– Owen
Feb 2 at 21:46


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3097385%2fwhy-dont-we-use-closed-covers-to-define-compactness-of-metric-space%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith