Can we deduce that morphisms in categories of structures should be “structure preserving”












2












$begingroup$


One of the fundamental ways category theory is used is to define categories of structures, where the morphisms are structure preserving maps. E.g. the category of topologies has continuous functions as morphisms.



But as far as I know, this is just a customary way that category theory can be used. We could just as well have said that the category of topologies has all functions as morphisms including non-continuous ones.



This would of course be useless, but apart from its practical use, is there also some sort of principled deduction that “structure preserving maps as morphisms” is somehow “the right way” or “a canonical way” of defining categories?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:23










  • $begingroup$
    @max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 12:32










  • $begingroup$
    Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:35










  • $begingroup$
    If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Feb 2 at 22:08
















2












$begingroup$


One of the fundamental ways category theory is used is to define categories of structures, where the morphisms are structure preserving maps. E.g. the category of topologies has continuous functions as morphisms.



But as far as I know, this is just a customary way that category theory can be used. We could just as well have said that the category of topologies has all functions as morphisms including non-continuous ones.



This would of course be useless, but apart from its practical use, is there also some sort of principled deduction that “structure preserving maps as morphisms” is somehow “the right way” or “a canonical way” of defining categories?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:23










  • $begingroup$
    @max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 12:32










  • $begingroup$
    Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:35










  • $begingroup$
    If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Feb 2 at 22:08














2












2








2





$begingroup$


One of the fundamental ways category theory is used is to define categories of structures, where the morphisms are structure preserving maps. E.g. the category of topologies has continuous functions as morphisms.



But as far as I know, this is just a customary way that category theory can be used. We could just as well have said that the category of topologies has all functions as morphisms including non-continuous ones.



This would of course be useless, but apart from its practical use, is there also some sort of principled deduction that “structure preserving maps as morphisms” is somehow “the right way” or “a canonical way” of defining categories?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




One of the fundamental ways category theory is used is to define categories of structures, where the morphisms are structure preserving maps. E.g. the category of topologies has continuous functions as morphisms.



But as far as I know, this is just a customary way that category theory can be used. We could just as well have said that the category of topologies has all functions as morphisms including non-continuous ones.



This would of course be useless, but apart from its practical use, is there also some sort of principled deduction that “structure preserving maps as morphisms” is somehow “the right way” or “a canonical way” of defining categories?







category-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jan 31 at 11:17









user56834user56834

3,42321253




3,42321253












  • $begingroup$
    It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:23










  • $begingroup$
    @max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 12:32










  • $begingroup$
    Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:35










  • $begingroup$
    If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Feb 2 at 22:08


















  • $begingroup$
    It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:23










  • $begingroup$
    @max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 12:32










  • $begingroup$
    Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Jan 31 at 12:35










  • $begingroup$
    If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
    $endgroup$
    – Malice Vidrine
    Feb 2 at 22:08
















$begingroup$
It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
$endgroup$
– Max
Jan 31 at 12:23




$begingroup$
It's just that we, mathematicians, are not interested in noncontinuous maps between topological spaces (most of the time); so what would be the point of considering this category ? Similarly if I called $X$ the set of subsets $F$ of $mathbb{R}$ such that if there exists a positive $xin F$, then $1in F$; then I can define $X$, but who cares ?
$endgroup$
– Max
Jan 31 at 12:23












$begingroup$
@max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
$endgroup$
– user56834
Jan 31 at 12:32




$begingroup$
@max, you are attacking straw man alternatives to the way it’s generally done. My question is motivated by the fact that I find it interesting that there is this general concept of “structure preserving maps” that are always used in category theory. This makes me wonder whether there is a deeper reason why structure preserving is a fundamental concept.
$endgroup$
– user56834
Jan 31 at 12:32












$begingroup$
Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
$endgroup$
– Max
Jan 31 at 12:35




$begingroup$
Structure preserving is a fundamental concept because we're interested in structures, there's not much more than that.
$endgroup$
– Max
Jan 31 at 12:35












$begingroup$
If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Feb 2 at 22:08




$begingroup$
If we were to deduce this, whatever we mean by that, we'd be saying that the categories that aren't structures with structure preserving maps are pathological. But very, very many categories that are not of this sort are actually interesting and useful.
$endgroup$
– Malice Vidrine
Feb 2 at 22:08










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















0












$begingroup$

Category theory doesn't really care about the structure of its objects and morphisms. For instance, the category of topological spaces is made up of all topological spaces and all continuous functions between them and at that point the category theory stops caring about what the objects and the arrows are. Just whether they exist, whether certain compositions are equal and so on.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 11:39










  • $begingroup$
    @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
    $endgroup$
    – Arthur
    Jan 31 at 12:07





















0












$begingroup$

There are two things to keep in mind.



First, as set theory treats sets as structure-less collections, i.e. lists of unnamed elements (it does not care if its elements are real numbers, apples, people), category theoretic objects have no internal structure.



The point of category theory is exactly to study structures without looking to their internal structure, but doing so makes impossible to deal with the structure preserving-property.



Another point of view is that the morphisms give the structure to the objects. There is also a very technical way to make this formal, you can find more in this answer.



Hope this helps.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$














    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3094784%2fcan-we-deduce-that-morphisms-in-categories-of-structures-should-be-structure-pr%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    0












    $begingroup$

    Category theory doesn't really care about the structure of its objects and morphisms. For instance, the category of topological spaces is made up of all topological spaces and all continuous functions between them and at that point the category theory stops caring about what the objects and the arrows are. Just whether they exist, whether certain compositions are equal and so on.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
      $endgroup$
      – user56834
      Jan 31 at 11:39










    • $begingroup$
      @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
      $endgroup$
      – Arthur
      Jan 31 at 12:07


















    0












    $begingroup$

    Category theory doesn't really care about the structure of its objects and morphisms. For instance, the category of topological spaces is made up of all topological spaces and all continuous functions between them and at that point the category theory stops caring about what the objects and the arrows are. Just whether they exist, whether certain compositions are equal and so on.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
      $endgroup$
      – user56834
      Jan 31 at 11:39










    • $begingroup$
      @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
      $endgroup$
      – Arthur
      Jan 31 at 12:07
















    0












    0








    0





    $begingroup$

    Category theory doesn't really care about the structure of its objects and morphisms. For instance, the category of topological spaces is made up of all topological spaces and all continuous functions between them and at that point the category theory stops caring about what the objects and the arrows are. Just whether they exist, whether certain compositions are equal and so on.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    Category theory doesn't really care about the structure of its objects and morphisms. For instance, the category of topological spaces is made up of all topological spaces and all continuous functions between them and at that point the category theory stops caring about what the objects and the arrows are. Just whether they exist, whether certain compositions are equal and so on.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jan 31 at 11:27









    ArthurArthur

    122k7122211




    122k7122211












    • $begingroup$
      I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
      $endgroup$
      – user56834
      Jan 31 at 11:39










    • $begingroup$
      @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
      $endgroup$
      – Arthur
      Jan 31 at 12:07




















    • $begingroup$
      I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
      $endgroup$
      – user56834
      Jan 31 at 11:39










    • $begingroup$
      @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
      $endgroup$
      – Arthur
      Jan 31 at 12:07


















    $begingroup$
    I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 11:39




    $begingroup$
    I know, but there is a reason that these categories are chosen and not others. I’m wondering whether there is something behind that practical reason.
    $endgroup$
    – user56834
    Jan 31 at 11:39












    $begingroup$
    @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
    $endgroup$
    – Arthur
    Jan 31 at 12:07






    $begingroup$
    @user56834 Even though the category itself doesn't explicitly carry any information about open sets or elements, suprisingly much of that information is encoded in the category structure. For instance, any topological space has exactly one morphism to any singleton space, and only singleton spaces have this property ("terminal object" is the categorical term). Once you have identified the singleton spaces, you can see constant maps as maps which "factor through" a singleton space. Many other things like injectivity or homeomorphicity are also encoded in similar fashion.
    $endgroup$
    – Arthur
    Jan 31 at 12:07













    0












    $begingroup$

    There are two things to keep in mind.



    First, as set theory treats sets as structure-less collections, i.e. lists of unnamed elements (it does not care if its elements are real numbers, apples, people), category theoretic objects have no internal structure.



    The point of category theory is exactly to study structures without looking to their internal structure, but doing so makes impossible to deal with the structure preserving-property.



    Another point of view is that the morphisms give the structure to the objects. There is also a very technical way to make this formal, you can find more in this answer.



    Hope this helps.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      0












      $begingroup$

      There are two things to keep in mind.



      First, as set theory treats sets as structure-less collections, i.e. lists of unnamed elements (it does not care if its elements are real numbers, apples, people), category theoretic objects have no internal structure.



      The point of category theory is exactly to study structures without looking to their internal structure, but doing so makes impossible to deal with the structure preserving-property.



      Another point of view is that the morphisms give the structure to the objects. There is also a very technical way to make this formal, you can find more in this answer.



      Hope this helps.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        There are two things to keep in mind.



        First, as set theory treats sets as structure-less collections, i.e. lists of unnamed elements (it does not care if its elements are real numbers, apples, people), category theoretic objects have no internal structure.



        The point of category theory is exactly to study structures without looking to their internal structure, but doing so makes impossible to deal with the structure preserving-property.



        Another point of view is that the morphisms give the structure to the objects. There is also a very technical way to make this formal, you can find more in this answer.



        Hope this helps.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        There are two things to keep in mind.



        First, as set theory treats sets as structure-less collections, i.e. lists of unnamed elements (it does not care if its elements are real numbers, apples, people), category theoretic objects have no internal structure.



        The point of category theory is exactly to study structures without looking to their internal structure, but doing so makes impossible to deal with the structure preserving-property.



        Another point of view is that the morphisms give the structure to the objects. There is also a very technical way to make this formal, you can find more in this answer.



        Hope this helps.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Feb 2 at 16:39









        Giorgio MossaGiorgio Mossa

        14.3k11749




        14.3k11749






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3094784%2fcan-we-deduce-that-morphisms-in-categories-of-structures-should-be-structure-pr%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

            How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

            in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith