Is the Carathéodory definition of Measurable set the most general?












2












$begingroup$


Does the Carathéodory definition of measurable set encompass the most sets possible?



By this I mean, are all the sets that are well behaved enough with pre-measure that they have all the properties that we want completely given by the Carathéodory criterion of measurability?



It's reasonable to require that measurable sets cut up measurable sets into components that sum up to the measure of the original set but it's not obvious why all sets need to be cut up in this way or why this is the most general definition of measurable set.



Why couldn't lebesgue measurable sets be some proper subset of an even less restrictive definition?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
    $endgroup$
    – Matt Samuel
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:05






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:29
















2












$begingroup$


Does the Carathéodory definition of measurable set encompass the most sets possible?



By this I mean, are all the sets that are well behaved enough with pre-measure that they have all the properties that we want completely given by the Carathéodory criterion of measurability?



It's reasonable to require that measurable sets cut up measurable sets into components that sum up to the measure of the original set but it's not obvious why all sets need to be cut up in this way or why this is the most general definition of measurable set.



Why couldn't lebesgue measurable sets be some proper subset of an even less restrictive definition?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
    $endgroup$
    – Matt Samuel
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:05






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:29














2












2








2





$begingroup$


Does the Carathéodory definition of measurable set encompass the most sets possible?



By this I mean, are all the sets that are well behaved enough with pre-measure that they have all the properties that we want completely given by the Carathéodory criterion of measurability?



It's reasonable to require that measurable sets cut up measurable sets into components that sum up to the measure of the original set but it's not obvious why all sets need to be cut up in this way or why this is the most general definition of measurable set.



Why couldn't lebesgue measurable sets be some proper subset of an even less restrictive definition?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




Does the Carathéodory definition of measurable set encompass the most sets possible?



By this I mean, are all the sets that are well behaved enough with pre-measure that they have all the properties that we want completely given by the Carathéodory criterion of measurability?



It's reasonable to require that measurable sets cut up measurable sets into components that sum up to the measure of the original set but it's not obvious why all sets need to be cut up in this way or why this is the most general definition of measurable set.



Why couldn't lebesgue measurable sets be some proper subset of an even less restrictive definition?







real-analysis measure-theory lebesgue-measure






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 19 '17 at 14:28









Trevor Gunn

14.5k32046




14.5k32046










asked Mar 12 '15 at 3:42









MichaelMichael

112




112








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
    $endgroup$
    – Matt Samuel
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:05






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:29














  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
    $endgroup$
    – Matt Samuel
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:05






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 12 '15 at 4:29








1




1




$begingroup$
Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
$endgroup$
– Matt Samuel
Mar 12 '15 at 4:05




$begingroup$
Yeah where did you get Cathedory from?
$endgroup$
– Matt Samuel
Mar 12 '15 at 4:05




1




1




$begingroup$
Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
$endgroup$
– Michael
Mar 12 '15 at 4:29




$begingroup$
Teacher always said it as Cathedory, it's kind of irrelevant nitpicking since the question is clear.
$endgroup$
– Michael
Mar 12 '15 at 4:29










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















4












$begingroup$

In some sense, you are asking the wrong question. We don't want the $sigma$-algebra of Lebesgue measurable sets to encompass too many sets - in fact, we prefer as few sets as reasonably permissible to be Lebesgue measurable. The Lebesgue measurability criterion is designed to exclude bad sets. The real question should be, "Does the definition of Lebesgue measurability exclude enough bad sets to be useful?"



The most important properties that we want out of Lebesgue measurability are the following:




  1. A product of bounded intervals should be measurable. Makes sense, since it's obvious how to define the volume of a $n$-dimensional box.


  2. There should be a reasonable definition of measure so that if we translate a measurable set, it shouldn't change the measure.



The Lebesgue measurable sets encompass all products of intervals but not too many more (they form a minimal good $sigma$-algebra containing products of intervals in some sense), and Lebesgue measure is a complete translation-invariant measure on the Lebesgue measurable sets. In fact, even better: one can prove it is the unique such measure. And as it turns out, it has several nice intuitive properties in addition: see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebesgue_measure#Properties. This is what I would consider a positive answer to the question I raised in the first paragraph.



In principle, one could easily come up with a less restrictive definition of measurable set. Take any non-measurable set, and use it and the Lebesgue $sigma$-algebra to generate a new $sigma$-algebra. But then, of course, the Carathéodory criterion no longer holds by fiat, and that's something we'd really like.



The best reason I see to assume the Carathéodory criterion is that the subsets in a measurable space that satisfy the criterion automatically form a $sigma$-algebra, so it actually makes sense to use it to define a $sigma$-algebra. (In particular, you use it to obtain countable additivity.) There are probably measure spaces that don't use the Carathéodory criterion to define measurability, but at least for Euclidean space the Carathéodory criterion makes too much sense to replace it with a weaker criterion for measurability.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$









  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 14 '15 at 3:20








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
    $endgroup$
    – Gyu Eun Lee
    Mar 14 '15 at 8:25






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:53












  • $begingroup$
    Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:56



















0












$begingroup$

The obvious reason is that "divide, measure each parts, and add up" is so essential to make a measure useful.



Intuitively, if you cut an apple into two pieces with a knife, you would expect the volumes of each parts adding up to the volume of that apple as a whole. It would be very weird if it does not.



Gyu Eun Lee is correct on this one: the point is not including as many sets as possible, the point is excluding as many sets as possible while keeping its (the idea of measures) usefulness. As Einstein once said: everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1186305%2fis-the-carath%25c3%25a9odory-definition-of-measurable-set-the-most-general%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    4












    $begingroup$

    In some sense, you are asking the wrong question. We don't want the $sigma$-algebra of Lebesgue measurable sets to encompass too many sets - in fact, we prefer as few sets as reasonably permissible to be Lebesgue measurable. The Lebesgue measurability criterion is designed to exclude bad sets. The real question should be, "Does the definition of Lebesgue measurability exclude enough bad sets to be useful?"



    The most important properties that we want out of Lebesgue measurability are the following:




    1. A product of bounded intervals should be measurable. Makes sense, since it's obvious how to define the volume of a $n$-dimensional box.


    2. There should be a reasonable definition of measure so that if we translate a measurable set, it shouldn't change the measure.



    The Lebesgue measurable sets encompass all products of intervals but not too many more (they form a minimal good $sigma$-algebra containing products of intervals in some sense), and Lebesgue measure is a complete translation-invariant measure on the Lebesgue measurable sets. In fact, even better: one can prove it is the unique such measure. And as it turns out, it has several nice intuitive properties in addition: see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebesgue_measure#Properties. This is what I would consider a positive answer to the question I raised in the first paragraph.



    In principle, one could easily come up with a less restrictive definition of measurable set. Take any non-measurable set, and use it and the Lebesgue $sigma$-algebra to generate a new $sigma$-algebra. But then, of course, the Carathéodory criterion no longer holds by fiat, and that's something we'd really like.



    The best reason I see to assume the Carathéodory criterion is that the subsets in a measurable space that satisfy the criterion automatically form a $sigma$-algebra, so it actually makes sense to use it to define a $sigma$-algebra. (In particular, you use it to obtain countable additivity.) There are probably measure spaces that don't use the Carathéodory criterion to define measurability, but at least for Euclidean space the Carathéodory criterion makes too much sense to replace it with a weaker criterion for measurability.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$









    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
      $endgroup$
      – Michael
      Mar 14 '15 at 3:20








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
      $endgroup$
      – Gyu Eun Lee
      Mar 14 '15 at 8:25






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:53












    • $begingroup$
      Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:56
















    4












    $begingroup$

    In some sense, you are asking the wrong question. We don't want the $sigma$-algebra of Lebesgue measurable sets to encompass too many sets - in fact, we prefer as few sets as reasonably permissible to be Lebesgue measurable. The Lebesgue measurability criterion is designed to exclude bad sets. The real question should be, "Does the definition of Lebesgue measurability exclude enough bad sets to be useful?"



    The most important properties that we want out of Lebesgue measurability are the following:




    1. A product of bounded intervals should be measurable. Makes sense, since it's obvious how to define the volume of a $n$-dimensional box.


    2. There should be a reasonable definition of measure so that if we translate a measurable set, it shouldn't change the measure.



    The Lebesgue measurable sets encompass all products of intervals but not too many more (they form a minimal good $sigma$-algebra containing products of intervals in some sense), and Lebesgue measure is a complete translation-invariant measure on the Lebesgue measurable sets. In fact, even better: one can prove it is the unique such measure. And as it turns out, it has several nice intuitive properties in addition: see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebesgue_measure#Properties. This is what I would consider a positive answer to the question I raised in the first paragraph.



    In principle, one could easily come up with a less restrictive definition of measurable set. Take any non-measurable set, and use it and the Lebesgue $sigma$-algebra to generate a new $sigma$-algebra. But then, of course, the Carathéodory criterion no longer holds by fiat, and that's something we'd really like.



    The best reason I see to assume the Carathéodory criterion is that the subsets in a measurable space that satisfy the criterion automatically form a $sigma$-algebra, so it actually makes sense to use it to define a $sigma$-algebra. (In particular, you use it to obtain countable additivity.) There are probably measure spaces that don't use the Carathéodory criterion to define measurability, but at least for Euclidean space the Carathéodory criterion makes too much sense to replace it with a weaker criterion for measurability.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$









    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
      $endgroup$
      – Michael
      Mar 14 '15 at 3:20








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
      $endgroup$
      – Gyu Eun Lee
      Mar 14 '15 at 8:25






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:53












    • $begingroup$
      Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:56














    4












    4








    4





    $begingroup$

    In some sense, you are asking the wrong question. We don't want the $sigma$-algebra of Lebesgue measurable sets to encompass too many sets - in fact, we prefer as few sets as reasonably permissible to be Lebesgue measurable. The Lebesgue measurability criterion is designed to exclude bad sets. The real question should be, "Does the definition of Lebesgue measurability exclude enough bad sets to be useful?"



    The most important properties that we want out of Lebesgue measurability are the following:




    1. A product of bounded intervals should be measurable. Makes sense, since it's obvious how to define the volume of a $n$-dimensional box.


    2. There should be a reasonable definition of measure so that if we translate a measurable set, it shouldn't change the measure.



    The Lebesgue measurable sets encompass all products of intervals but not too many more (they form a minimal good $sigma$-algebra containing products of intervals in some sense), and Lebesgue measure is a complete translation-invariant measure on the Lebesgue measurable sets. In fact, even better: one can prove it is the unique such measure. And as it turns out, it has several nice intuitive properties in addition: see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebesgue_measure#Properties. This is what I would consider a positive answer to the question I raised in the first paragraph.



    In principle, one could easily come up with a less restrictive definition of measurable set. Take any non-measurable set, and use it and the Lebesgue $sigma$-algebra to generate a new $sigma$-algebra. But then, of course, the Carathéodory criterion no longer holds by fiat, and that's something we'd really like.



    The best reason I see to assume the Carathéodory criterion is that the subsets in a measurable space that satisfy the criterion automatically form a $sigma$-algebra, so it actually makes sense to use it to define a $sigma$-algebra. (In particular, you use it to obtain countable additivity.) There are probably measure spaces that don't use the Carathéodory criterion to define measurability, but at least for Euclidean space the Carathéodory criterion makes too much sense to replace it with a weaker criterion for measurability.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    In some sense, you are asking the wrong question. We don't want the $sigma$-algebra of Lebesgue measurable sets to encompass too many sets - in fact, we prefer as few sets as reasonably permissible to be Lebesgue measurable. The Lebesgue measurability criterion is designed to exclude bad sets. The real question should be, "Does the definition of Lebesgue measurability exclude enough bad sets to be useful?"



    The most important properties that we want out of Lebesgue measurability are the following:




    1. A product of bounded intervals should be measurable. Makes sense, since it's obvious how to define the volume of a $n$-dimensional box.


    2. There should be a reasonable definition of measure so that if we translate a measurable set, it shouldn't change the measure.



    The Lebesgue measurable sets encompass all products of intervals but not too many more (they form a minimal good $sigma$-algebra containing products of intervals in some sense), and Lebesgue measure is a complete translation-invariant measure on the Lebesgue measurable sets. In fact, even better: one can prove it is the unique such measure. And as it turns out, it has several nice intuitive properties in addition: see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lebesgue_measure#Properties. This is what I would consider a positive answer to the question I raised in the first paragraph.



    In principle, one could easily come up with a less restrictive definition of measurable set. Take any non-measurable set, and use it and the Lebesgue $sigma$-algebra to generate a new $sigma$-algebra. But then, of course, the Carathéodory criterion no longer holds by fiat, and that's something we'd really like.



    The best reason I see to assume the Carathéodory criterion is that the subsets in a measurable space that satisfy the criterion automatically form a $sigma$-algebra, so it actually makes sense to use it to define a $sigma$-algebra. (In particular, you use it to obtain countable additivity.) There are probably measure spaces that don't use the Carathéodory criterion to define measurability, but at least for Euclidean space the Carathéodory criterion makes too much sense to replace it with a weaker criterion for measurability.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Mar 13 '15 at 7:03









    Gyu Eun LeeGyu Eun Lee

    13.2k2353




    13.2k2353








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
      $endgroup$
      – Michael
      Mar 14 '15 at 3:20








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
      $endgroup$
      – Gyu Eun Lee
      Mar 14 '15 at 8:25






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:53












    • $begingroup$
      Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:56














    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
      $endgroup$
      – Michael
      Mar 14 '15 at 3:20








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
      $endgroup$
      – Gyu Eun Lee
      Mar 14 '15 at 8:25






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:53












    • $begingroup$
      Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
      $endgroup$
      – fourierwho
      Jul 19 '17 at 17:56








    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 14 '15 at 3:20






    $begingroup$
    I can't help but disagree with the assertion that we don't want as many sets as measurable as possible. Isn't it the goal of measure theory to measure as many sets as possible?
    $endgroup$
    – Michael
    Mar 14 '15 at 3:20






    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
    $endgroup$
    – Gyu Eun Lee
    Mar 14 '15 at 8:25




    $begingroup$
    No, the exact opposite. The whole issue with our naive notion of measure was that in general, subsets of Euclidean space can be (and usually are) quite pathological to the point of violating all of our intuition about volume (e.g. Vitali set). To put this another way, including more sets in our class of measurable sets makes it harder for our measure to have nice properties like translation invariance. If our goal is a measure we can work with we should only include as many sets as we need, to avoid screwing up the measure.
    $endgroup$
    – Gyu Eun Lee
    Mar 14 '15 at 8:25




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:53






    $begingroup$
    I'm not sure I agree on your philosophy here: we know that we can't get a measure with the right properties on the entire power set of $mathbb{R}$, but why shouldn't it be a fortunate state of affairs if we could? (As it happens, pathological examples convince us this is impossible, but why wouldn't we want to measure pathological sets if the universe were different and the axioms, therefore, said we could?)
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:53














    $begingroup$
    Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:56




    $begingroup$
    Incidentally, in your fourth paragraph, it's not clear that we could extend Lebesgue measure to this new $sigma$-algebra.
    $endgroup$
    – fourierwho
    Jul 19 '17 at 17:56











    0












    $begingroup$

    The obvious reason is that "divide, measure each parts, and add up" is so essential to make a measure useful.



    Intuitively, if you cut an apple into two pieces with a knife, you would expect the volumes of each parts adding up to the volume of that apple as a whole. It would be very weird if it does not.



    Gyu Eun Lee is correct on this one: the point is not including as many sets as possible, the point is excluding as many sets as possible while keeping its (the idea of measures) usefulness. As Einstein once said: everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      0












      $begingroup$

      The obvious reason is that "divide, measure each parts, and add up" is so essential to make a measure useful.



      Intuitively, if you cut an apple into two pieces with a knife, you would expect the volumes of each parts adding up to the volume of that apple as a whole. It would be very weird if it does not.



      Gyu Eun Lee is correct on this one: the point is not including as many sets as possible, the point is excluding as many sets as possible while keeping its (the idea of measures) usefulness. As Einstein once said: everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        The obvious reason is that "divide, measure each parts, and add up" is so essential to make a measure useful.



        Intuitively, if you cut an apple into two pieces with a knife, you would expect the volumes of each parts adding up to the volume of that apple as a whole. It would be very weird if it does not.



        Gyu Eun Lee is correct on this one: the point is not including as many sets as possible, the point is excluding as many sets as possible while keeping its (the idea of measures) usefulness. As Einstein once said: everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        The obvious reason is that "divide, measure each parts, and add up" is so essential to make a measure useful.



        Intuitively, if you cut an apple into two pieces with a knife, you would expect the volumes of each parts adding up to the volume of that apple as a whole. It would be very weird if it does not.



        Gyu Eun Lee is correct on this one: the point is not including as many sets as possible, the point is excluding as many sets as possible while keeping its (the idea of measures) usefulness. As Einstein once said: everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Jan 10 at 7:17









        John Z. LiJohn Z. Li

        194




        194






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1186305%2fis-the-carath%25c3%25a9odory-definition-of-measurable-set-the-most-general%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

            How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

            in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith