Choosing a Cauchy sequence for a real












1












$begingroup$


It is easy to form in ZF, for each real $a$, a "canonical" Cauchy sequence that converges to $a$. For example, one can take the sequence of finite initial segments of the decimal expansion of $a$, being careful when $a$ is a base-10 rational to pick one of the two decimal expansions explicitly.



But what if we are given a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals, all converging to the same real. The set might not contain all the Cauchy sequences for that real. How hard is it to pick a "canonical" representative from the sequences that are in the set?



To make this question precise: consider a family of sets $C$ so that each $X in C$ is a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals that all converge to the same real $a(X)$. Note that $X$ is not required to have the entire set of Cauchy sequences for $a(X)$. Does ZF prove the existence of a choice function for each family $C$ of this kind?



There are two aspects of Cauchy sequences that make this problem interesting. First, every infinite subsequence of a Cauchy sequence is again a Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "minimal" sequence. Also, we may prepend any finite sequence to a Cauchy sequence to yield a new Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "maximal" sequence. Cauchy sequences are very slippery in this way.



Dedekind cuts behave differently: once we specify whether cuts for rationals can have a maximum element, we have a unique Dedekind cut for each real, whereas we always have infinitely many Cauchy sequences.



I have a vague memory of encountering something similar to this question in the past, but I cannot remember any details. It also seems to have a flavor related to Borel equivalence relations, although this question is not written in that way.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$

















    1












    $begingroup$


    It is easy to form in ZF, for each real $a$, a "canonical" Cauchy sequence that converges to $a$. For example, one can take the sequence of finite initial segments of the decimal expansion of $a$, being careful when $a$ is a base-10 rational to pick one of the two decimal expansions explicitly.



    But what if we are given a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals, all converging to the same real. The set might not contain all the Cauchy sequences for that real. How hard is it to pick a "canonical" representative from the sequences that are in the set?



    To make this question precise: consider a family of sets $C$ so that each $X in C$ is a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals that all converge to the same real $a(X)$. Note that $X$ is not required to have the entire set of Cauchy sequences for $a(X)$. Does ZF prove the existence of a choice function for each family $C$ of this kind?



    There are two aspects of Cauchy sequences that make this problem interesting. First, every infinite subsequence of a Cauchy sequence is again a Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "minimal" sequence. Also, we may prepend any finite sequence to a Cauchy sequence to yield a new Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "maximal" sequence. Cauchy sequences are very slippery in this way.



    Dedekind cuts behave differently: once we specify whether cuts for rationals can have a maximum element, we have a unique Dedekind cut for each real, whereas we always have infinitely many Cauchy sequences.



    I have a vague memory of encountering something similar to this question in the past, but I cannot remember any details. It also seems to have a flavor related to Borel equivalence relations, although this question is not written in that way.










    share|cite|improve this question











    $endgroup$















      1












      1








      1


      1



      $begingroup$


      It is easy to form in ZF, for each real $a$, a "canonical" Cauchy sequence that converges to $a$. For example, one can take the sequence of finite initial segments of the decimal expansion of $a$, being careful when $a$ is a base-10 rational to pick one of the two decimal expansions explicitly.



      But what if we are given a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals, all converging to the same real. The set might not contain all the Cauchy sequences for that real. How hard is it to pick a "canonical" representative from the sequences that are in the set?



      To make this question precise: consider a family of sets $C$ so that each $X in C$ is a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals that all converge to the same real $a(X)$. Note that $X$ is not required to have the entire set of Cauchy sequences for $a(X)$. Does ZF prove the existence of a choice function for each family $C$ of this kind?



      There are two aspects of Cauchy sequences that make this problem interesting. First, every infinite subsequence of a Cauchy sequence is again a Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "minimal" sequence. Also, we may prepend any finite sequence to a Cauchy sequence to yield a new Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "maximal" sequence. Cauchy sequences are very slippery in this way.



      Dedekind cuts behave differently: once we specify whether cuts for rationals can have a maximum element, we have a unique Dedekind cut for each real, whereas we always have infinitely many Cauchy sequences.



      I have a vague memory of encountering something similar to this question in the past, but I cannot remember any details. It also seems to have a flavor related to Borel equivalence relations, although this question is not written in that way.










      share|cite|improve this question











      $endgroup$




      It is easy to form in ZF, for each real $a$, a "canonical" Cauchy sequence that converges to $a$. For example, one can take the sequence of finite initial segments of the decimal expansion of $a$, being careful when $a$ is a base-10 rational to pick one of the two decimal expansions explicitly.



      But what if we are given a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals, all converging to the same real. The set might not contain all the Cauchy sequences for that real. How hard is it to pick a "canonical" representative from the sequences that are in the set?



      To make this question precise: consider a family of sets $C$ so that each $X in C$ is a set of Cauchy sequences of rationals that all converge to the same real $a(X)$. Note that $X$ is not required to have the entire set of Cauchy sequences for $a(X)$. Does ZF prove the existence of a choice function for each family $C$ of this kind?



      There are two aspects of Cauchy sequences that make this problem interesting. First, every infinite subsequence of a Cauchy sequence is again a Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "minimal" sequence. Also, we may prepend any finite sequence to a Cauchy sequence to yield a new Cauchy sequence converging to the same real. So we cannot hope for a "maximal" sequence. Cauchy sequences are very slippery in this way.



      Dedekind cuts behave differently: once we specify whether cuts for rationals can have a maximum element, we have a unique Dedekind cut for each real, whereas we always have infinitely many Cauchy sequences.



      I have a vague memory of encountering something similar to this question in the past, but I cannot remember any details. It also seems to have a flavor related to Borel equivalence relations, although this question is not written in that way.







      elementary-set-theory logic axiom-of-choice






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited Jan 27 at 17:09







      Carl Mummert

















      asked May 4 '15 at 17:52









      Carl MummertCarl Mummert

      67.6k7133252




      67.6k7133252






















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          1












          $begingroup$

          Let me take Lord_Farin's answer, and crank it all the way to $2^{aleph_0}$.



          Suppose that we could have chosen from any family of Cauchy sequences. Fix for each real number a canonical Cauchy sequence of rationals $r_n$ which is strictly increasing. This is of course doable without choice.



          Now suppose that $A_rsubseteq 2^omegasetminus 2^{<omega}$ is non-empty for each $rinBbb R$, then consider $C_r={langle r_nmid a_nneq 0ranglemidlangle a_nranglein A_r}$. Namely we encode each $ain A_r$ as a subsequence of $r_n$, with the assumption that $a$ is not eventually $0$.



          By the assumption there will be a choice from each $C_r$, and then we can easily decode this into a choice from $A_r$. So we have proved the axiom of choice for families of size $leq2^{aleph_0}$ of sets of reals. And of course we cannot even prove choice for countable families of sets of reals in $sf ZF$ itself.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:25






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 18:38












          • $begingroup$
            Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:44






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 19:05






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
            $endgroup$
            – Henning Makholm
            May 4 '15 at 19:22





















          3












          $begingroup$

          Such a choice mechanism would translate to a canonical choice for a function $Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$ from a given set $S$ of such functions. If I'm not mistaken, this is some nontrivial choice principle (and if I am, please do correct me).



          Given $f: Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$, define: $$b_f (n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$



          Now define $s_f(n) = sumlimits_{i=0}^n b_f(i)$. Then for all $f$: $$lim_{ntoinfty} s_f(n) = 2$$
          and $f leftrightarrow s_f$ is a bijective correspondence. Hence a choice function for each set ${s_f: f in S}$ amounts to a choice function for each $S subseteq (Bbb N_{>0})^{Bbb N}$.





          By defining, for $f: Bbb N to 2$: $$b_f(n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = k + sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ the argument seems to carry over to $2^{Bbb N}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 19:11












          • $begingroup$
            @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
            $endgroup$
            – Lord_Farin
            May 4 '15 at 19:15










          • $begingroup$
            So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:35










          • $begingroup$
            @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:37











          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














          draft saved

          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1266792%2fchoosing-a-cauchy-sequence-for-a-real%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes








          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          1












          $begingroup$

          Let me take Lord_Farin's answer, and crank it all the way to $2^{aleph_0}$.



          Suppose that we could have chosen from any family of Cauchy sequences. Fix for each real number a canonical Cauchy sequence of rationals $r_n$ which is strictly increasing. This is of course doable without choice.



          Now suppose that $A_rsubseteq 2^omegasetminus 2^{<omega}$ is non-empty for each $rinBbb R$, then consider $C_r={langle r_nmid a_nneq 0ranglemidlangle a_nranglein A_r}$. Namely we encode each $ain A_r$ as a subsequence of $r_n$, with the assumption that $a$ is not eventually $0$.



          By the assumption there will be a choice from each $C_r$, and then we can easily decode this into a choice from $A_r$. So we have proved the axiom of choice for families of size $leq2^{aleph_0}$ of sets of reals. And of course we cannot even prove choice for countable families of sets of reals in $sf ZF$ itself.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:25






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 18:38












          • $begingroup$
            Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:44






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 19:05






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
            $endgroup$
            – Henning Makholm
            May 4 '15 at 19:22


















          1












          $begingroup$

          Let me take Lord_Farin's answer, and crank it all the way to $2^{aleph_0}$.



          Suppose that we could have chosen from any family of Cauchy sequences. Fix for each real number a canonical Cauchy sequence of rationals $r_n$ which is strictly increasing. This is of course doable without choice.



          Now suppose that $A_rsubseteq 2^omegasetminus 2^{<omega}$ is non-empty for each $rinBbb R$, then consider $C_r={langle r_nmid a_nneq 0ranglemidlangle a_nranglein A_r}$. Namely we encode each $ain A_r$ as a subsequence of $r_n$, with the assumption that $a$ is not eventually $0$.



          By the assumption there will be a choice from each $C_r$, and then we can easily decode this into a choice from $A_r$. So we have proved the axiom of choice for families of size $leq2^{aleph_0}$ of sets of reals. And of course we cannot even prove choice for countable families of sets of reals in $sf ZF$ itself.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:25






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 18:38












          • $begingroup$
            Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:44






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 19:05






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
            $endgroup$
            – Henning Makholm
            May 4 '15 at 19:22
















          1












          1








          1





          $begingroup$

          Let me take Lord_Farin's answer, and crank it all the way to $2^{aleph_0}$.



          Suppose that we could have chosen from any family of Cauchy sequences. Fix for each real number a canonical Cauchy sequence of rationals $r_n$ which is strictly increasing. This is of course doable without choice.



          Now suppose that $A_rsubseteq 2^omegasetminus 2^{<omega}$ is non-empty for each $rinBbb R$, then consider $C_r={langle r_nmid a_nneq 0ranglemidlangle a_nranglein A_r}$. Namely we encode each $ain A_r$ as a subsequence of $r_n$, with the assumption that $a$ is not eventually $0$.



          By the assumption there will be a choice from each $C_r$, and then we can easily decode this into a choice from $A_r$. So we have proved the axiom of choice for families of size $leq2^{aleph_0}$ of sets of reals. And of course we cannot even prove choice for countable families of sets of reals in $sf ZF$ itself.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          Let me take Lord_Farin's answer, and crank it all the way to $2^{aleph_0}$.



          Suppose that we could have chosen from any family of Cauchy sequences. Fix for each real number a canonical Cauchy sequence of rationals $r_n$ which is strictly increasing. This is of course doable without choice.



          Now suppose that $A_rsubseteq 2^omegasetminus 2^{<omega}$ is non-empty for each $rinBbb R$, then consider $C_r={langle r_nmid a_nneq 0ranglemidlangle a_nranglein A_r}$. Namely we encode each $ain A_r$ as a subsequence of $r_n$, with the assumption that $a$ is not eventually $0$.



          By the assumption there will be a choice from each $C_r$, and then we can easily decode this into a choice from $A_r$. So we have proved the axiom of choice for families of size $leq2^{aleph_0}$ of sets of reals. And of course we cannot even prove choice for countable families of sets of reals in $sf ZF$ itself.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited May 4 '15 at 20:53

























          answered May 4 '15 at 18:22









          Asaf KaragilaAsaf Karagila

          307k33439770




          307k33439770












          • $begingroup$
            There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:25






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 18:38












          • $begingroup$
            Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:44






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 19:05






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
            $endgroup$
            – Henning Makholm
            May 4 '15 at 19:22




















          • $begingroup$
            There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:25






          • 2




            $begingroup$
            I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 18:38












          • $begingroup$
            Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 18:44






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 19:05






          • 1




            $begingroup$
            No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
            $endgroup$
            – Henning Makholm
            May 4 '15 at 19:22


















          $begingroup$
          There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 18:25




          $begingroup$
          There might be some minor corrections to this idea, but I need to write an exercise, and it's getting late. So I'll address them once that part of the evening is over!
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 18:25




          2




          2




          $begingroup$
          I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
          $endgroup$
          – Carl Mummert
          May 4 '15 at 18:38






          $begingroup$
          I don't follow yet; does this give back a Cauchy sequence that was in the original set of Cauchy sequences, which may not be the full equivalence class?
          $endgroup$
          – Carl Mummert
          May 4 '15 at 18:38














          $begingroup$
          Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 18:44




          $begingroup$
          Oh. I sort of missed that "subsets of equivalence classes" part. No, I don't see at all why there can be canonical choices for subsets of equivalence classes. I answered indeed for "choice for the equivalence classes". Should I delete this answer?
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 18:44




          1




          1




          $begingroup$
          All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 19:05




          $begingroup$
          All better. I hope. Now I can finally quell my mind and write that exercise about definable truth predicates in $Bbb N$. :-)
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 19:05




          1




          1




          $begingroup$
          No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
          $endgroup$
          – Henning Makholm
          May 4 '15 at 19:22






          $begingroup$
          No, this won't work. Suppose $C={f_1,f_2,f_3,ldots}$ where $$f_k(m)=begin{cases} 0 & m<k \ 1 & text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ and use an enumeration of $mathbb Q$ where $0$ comes before $1$. Then your $bigcap C_n$ is empty!
          $endgroup$
          – Henning Makholm
          May 4 '15 at 19:22













          3












          $begingroup$

          Such a choice mechanism would translate to a canonical choice for a function $Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$ from a given set $S$ of such functions. If I'm not mistaken, this is some nontrivial choice principle (and if I am, please do correct me).



          Given $f: Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$, define: $$b_f (n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$



          Now define $s_f(n) = sumlimits_{i=0}^n b_f(i)$. Then for all $f$: $$lim_{ntoinfty} s_f(n) = 2$$
          and $f leftrightarrow s_f$ is a bijective correspondence. Hence a choice function for each set ${s_f: f in S}$ amounts to a choice function for each $S subseteq (Bbb N_{>0})^{Bbb N}$.





          By defining, for $f: Bbb N to 2$: $$b_f(n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = k + sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ the argument seems to carry over to $2^{Bbb N}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 19:11












          • $begingroup$
            @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
            $endgroup$
            – Lord_Farin
            May 4 '15 at 19:15










          • $begingroup$
            So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:35










          • $begingroup$
            @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:37
















          3












          $begingroup$

          Such a choice mechanism would translate to a canonical choice for a function $Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$ from a given set $S$ of such functions. If I'm not mistaken, this is some nontrivial choice principle (and if I am, please do correct me).



          Given $f: Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$, define: $$b_f (n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$



          Now define $s_f(n) = sumlimits_{i=0}^n b_f(i)$. Then for all $f$: $$lim_{ntoinfty} s_f(n) = 2$$
          and $f leftrightarrow s_f$ is a bijective correspondence. Hence a choice function for each set ${s_f: f in S}$ amounts to a choice function for each $S subseteq (Bbb N_{>0})^{Bbb N}$.





          By defining, for $f: Bbb N to 2$: $$b_f(n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = k + sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ the argument seems to carry over to $2^{Bbb N}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 19:11












          • $begingroup$
            @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
            $endgroup$
            – Lord_Farin
            May 4 '15 at 19:15










          • $begingroup$
            So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:35










          • $begingroup$
            @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:37














          3












          3








          3





          $begingroup$

          Such a choice mechanism would translate to a canonical choice for a function $Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$ from a given set $S$ of such functions. If I'm not mistaken, this is some nontrivial choice principle (and if I am, please do correct me).



          Given $f: Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$, define: $$b_f (n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$



          Now define $s_f(n) = sumlimits_{i=0}^n b_f(i)$. Then for all $f$: $$lim_{ntoinfty} s_f(n) = 2$$
          and $f leftrightarrow s_f$ is a bijective correspondence. Hence a choice function for each set ${s_f: f in S}$ amounts to a choice function for each $S subseteq (Bbb N_{>0})^{Bbb N}$.





          By defining, for $f: Bbb N to 2$: $$b_f(n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = k + sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ the argument seems to carry over to $2^{Bbb N}$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          Such a choice mechanism would translate to a canonical choice for a function $Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$ from a given set $S$ of such functions. If I'm not mistaken, this is some nontrivial choice principle (and if I am, please do correct me).



          Given $f: Bbb N to Bbb N_{>0}$, define: $$b_f (n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$



          Now define $s_f(n) = sumlimits_{i=0}^n b_f(i)$. Then for all $f$: $$lim_{ntoinfty} s_f(n) = 2$$
          and $f leftrightarrow s_f$ is a bijective correspondence. Hence a choice function for each set ${s_f: f in S}$ amounts to a choice function for each $S subseteq (Bbb N_{>0})^{Bbb N}$.





          By defining, for $f: Bbb N to 2$: $$b_f(n) = begin{cases}2^{-k} &: n = k + sumlimits_{i=0}^k f(i) \0&: text{otherwise}end{cases}$$ the argument seems to carry over to $2^{Bbb N}$.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited May 4 '15 at 19:18

























          answered May 4 '15 at 19:06









          Lord_FarinLord_Farin

          15.7k636110




          15.7k636110












          • $begingroup$
            I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 19:11












          • $begingroup$
            @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
            $endgroup$
            – Lord_Farin
            May 4 '15 at 19:15










          • $begingroup$
            So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:35










          • $begingroup$
            @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:37


















          • $begingroup$
            I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
            $endgroup$
            – Carl Mummert
            May 4 '15 at 19:11












          • $begingroup$
            @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
            $endgroup$
            – Lord_Farin
            May 4 '15 at 19:15










          • $begingroup$
            So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:35










          • $begingroup$
            @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
            $endgroup$
            – Asaf Karagila
            May 4 '15 at 20:37
















          $begingroup$
          I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
          $endgroup$
          – Carl Mummert
          May 4 '15 at 19:11






          $begingroup$
          I believe the correspondence here is correct (and $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}_{>0}$ is in effective bijection with $mathbb{N} to mathbb{N}$ via the math $T(f)(x) = f(x) - 1$. So the argument carries over to $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. But then the argument in Asaf's answer seems to apply equally well, which leads to a fact I had not realized, which is that ZF proves choice for families of subsets of $mathbb{N}^mathbb{N}$. (I think this answer is very relevant, by the way; +1)
          $endgroup$
          – Carl Mummert
          May 4 '15 at 19:11














          $begingroup$
          @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
          $endgroup$
          – Lord_Farin
          May 4 '15 at 19:15




          $begingroup$
          @Carl I was also straining my mind to see the possible flaw in Asaf's answer, but it seems fine. Thus, we seem to have proven choice for subsets of $Bbb N^{Bbb N}$ :).
          $endgroup$
          – Lord_Farin
          May 4 '15 at 19:15












          $begingroup$
          So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 20:35




          $begingroup$
          So you translate a set functions into Cauchy sequences approaching $2$. I'm not sure this would be an issue. But I do agree that given a countable collection of sets of functions, translating each to a set of Cauchy sequences approaching $n$; then being able to choose would prove at least countable choice for sets of reals, which we know is impossible to prove in $sf ZF$.
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 20:35












          $begingroup$
          @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 20:37




          $begingroup$
          @Carl: I originally had a hunch that this would be unprovable. But I managed to convince myself that it can be done. I blame the time stress that I needed to write an exercise! :-)
          $endgroup$
          – Asaf Karagila
          May 4 '15 at 20:37


















          draft saved

          draft discarded




















































          Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1266792%2fchoosing-a-cauchy-sequence-for-a-real%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

          Npm cannot find a required file even through it is in the searched directory

          in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith