Proof of Fundamental Theorem of Finite Abelian Groups












4












$begingroup$


Statement: Let G be an Abelian group of prime-power order and let a be an element of maximum order in G. Then G can be written in the form $a times K$.



Proof: We denote |G| by p^n and induct on n. If n = 1, then G = $langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random m for the order of a? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]



Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in G. [Question: How, if |G| = p^k?]
We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
Now among all elements of G, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which b is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which b is chosen? Why does b^p lie in the set generated by a? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order p according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies b^p = e?]



Say $b^p = a^i$. Notice that $e=b^{p^m}=(b^p)^{p^{m-1}} = (a^i)^{p^{m-1}}$, so $|a^i| leq p^{m-1}$.
Thus, $a^i$ is not a generator of . Therefore, $gcd(p^m,i) neq 1$. This proves that $p$ divides $i$. Let $i = pj$. Then $b^p = a^i = a^{pj}$.



Consider the element $c = a^{-j}b$. $c$ is not in .
$c^p = a^{-jp}b^p$. Thus $c$ is an element of order p such that c is not in . Since b was chosen to have minimal order, we can finally say that b has an order of p.
It now follows that $langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$, because any non-identity element of the intersection would generate $langle b rangle$ and thus contradict that b lies in .



Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in G.
If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]



This means that $(alangle b rangle)^{p^{m-1}} = a^{p^{m-1}}langle b rangle = langle b rangle$. This implies that the order of a is $p^{m-1}$, which is absurd. So order of a-bar is equal to order of a which is $p^m$.
Therefore $overline{a}$ is an element of maximum order in $overline{G}$.



By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is K? How are we even defining K in the steps below?]



Let K be the pullback of $overline{K}$ under the natural homomorphism from G to G-bar.



We claim that $langle a rangle cap K = {e}$. For if $x in langle overline{a} rangle cap overline{K} = {e} = langle b rangle$ and $x in langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$.



It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = <a>K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.



I am currently teaching myself abstract algebra and real analysis and this proof has be confused for a while now. I apologize for the length of the post, but I could not think of any other way to convey my doubts in any concise manner.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 13:53












  • $begingroup$
    The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
    $endgroup$
    – Sat D
    May 8 '17 at 14:32










  • $begingroup$
    You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 14:41










  • $begingroup$
    See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
    $endgroup$
    – lhf
    Jan 7 at 9:35
















4












$begingroup$


Statement: Let G be an Abelian group of prime-power order and let a be an element of maximum order in G. Then G can be written in the form $a times K$.



Proof: We denote |G| by p^n and induct on n. If n = 1, then G = $langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random m for the order of a? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]



Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in G. [Question: How, if |G| = p^k?]
We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
Now among all elements of G, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which b is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which b is chosen? Why does b^p lie in the set generated by a? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order p according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies b^p = e?]



Say $b^p = a^i$. Notice that $e=b^{p^m}=(b^p)^{p^{m-1}} = (a^i)^{p^{m-1}}$, so $|a^i| leq p^{m-1}$.
Thus, $a^i$ is not a generator of . Therefore, $gcd(p^m,i) neq 1$. This proves that $p$ divides $i$. Let $i = pj$. Then $b^p = a^i = a^{pj}$.



Consider the element $c = a^{-j}b$. $c$ is not in .
$c^p = a^{-jp}b^p$. Thus $c$ is an element of order p such that c is not in . Since b was chosen to have minimal order, we can finally say that b has an order of p.
It now follows that $langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$, because any non-identity element of the intersection would generate $langle b rangle$ and thus contradict that b lies in .



Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in G.
If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]



This means that $(alangle b rangle)^{p^{m-1}} = a^{p^{m-1}}langle b rangle = langle b rangle$. This implies that the order of a is $p^{m-1}$, which is absurd. So order of a-bar is equal to order of a which is $p^m$.
Therefore $overline{a}$ is an element of maximum order in $overline{G}$.



By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is K? How are we even defining K in the steps below?]



Let K be the pullback of $overline{K}$ under the natural homomorphism from G to G-bar.



We claim that $langle a rangle cap K = {e}$. For if $x in langle overline{a} rangle cap overline{K} = {e} = langle b rangle$ and $x in langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$.



It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = <a>K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.



I am currently teaching myself abstract algebra and real analysis and this proof has be confused for a while now. I apologize for the length of the post, but I could not think of any other way to convey my doubts in any concise manner.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 13:53












  • $begingroup$
    The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
    $endgroup$
    – Sat D
    May 8 '17 at 14:32










  • $begingroup$
    You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 14:41










  • $begingroup$
    See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
    $endgroup$
    – lhf
    Jan 7 at 9:35














4












4








4


1



$begingroup$


Statement: Let G be an Abelian group of prime-power order and let a be an element of maximum order in G. Then G can be written in the form $a times K$.



Proof: We denote |G| by p^n and induct on n. If n = 1, then G = $langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random m for the order of a? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]



Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in G. [Question: How, if |G| = p^k?]
We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
Now among all elements of G, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which b is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which b is chosen? Why does b^p lie in the set generated by a? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order p according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies b^p = e?]



Say $b^p = a^i$. Notice that $e=b^{p^m}=(b^p)^{p^{m-1}} = (a^i)^{p^{m-1}}$, so $|a^i| leq p^{m-1}$.
Thus, $a^i$ is not a generator of . Therefore, $gcd(p^m,i) neq 1$. This proves that $p$ divides $i$. Let $i = pj$. Then $b^p = a^i = a^{pj}$.



Consider the element $c = a^{-j}b$. $c$ is not in .
$c^p = a^{-jp}b^p$. Thus $c$ is an element of order p such that c is not in . Since b was chosen to have minimal order, we can finally say that b has an order of p.
It now follows that $langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$, because any non-identity element of the intersection would generate $langle b rangle$ and thus contradict that b lies in .



Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in G.
If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]



This means that $(alangle b rangle)^{p^{m-1}} = a^{p^{m-1}}langle b rangle = langle b rangle$. This implies that the order of a is $p^{m-1}$, which is absurd. So order of a-bar is equal to order of a which is $p^m$.
Therefore $overline{a}$ is an element of maximum order in $overline{G}$.



By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is K? How are we even defining K in the steps below?]



Let K be the pullback of $overline{K}$ under the natural homomorphism from G to G-bar.



We claim that $langle a rangle cap K = {e}$. For if $x in langle overline{a} rangle cap overline{K} = {e} = langle b rangle$ and $x in langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$.



It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = <a>K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.



I am currently teaching myself abstract algebra and real analysis and this proof has be confused for a while now. I apologize for the length of the post, but I could not think of any other way to convey my doubts in any concise manner.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




Statement: Let G be an Abelian group of prime-power order and let a be an element of maximum order in G. Then G can be written in the form $a times K$.



Proof: We denote |G| by p^n and induct on n. If n = 1, then G = $langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random m for the order of a? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]



Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in G. [Question: How, if |G| = p^k?]
We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
Now among all elements of G, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which b is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which b is chosen? Why does b^p lie in the set generated by a? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order p according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies b^p = e?]



Say $b^p = a^i$. Notice that $e=b^{p^m}=(b^p)^{p^{m-1}} = (a^i)^{p^{m-1}}$, so $|a^i| leq p^{m-1}$.
Thus, $a^i$ is not a generator of . Therefore, $gcd(p^m,i) neq 1$. This proves that $p$ divides $i$. Let $i = pj$. Then $b^p = a^i = a^{pj}$.



Consider the element $c = a^{-j}b$. $c$ is not in .
$c^p = a^{-jp}b^p$. Thus $c$ is an element of order p such that c is not in . Since b was chosen to have minimal order, we can finally say that b has an order of p.
It now follows that $langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$, because any non-identity element of the intersection would generate $langle b rangle$ and thus contradict that b lies in .



Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in G.
If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]



This means that $(alangle b rangle)^{p^{m-1}} = a^{p^{m-1}}langle b rangle = langle b rangle$. This implies that the order of a is $p^{m-1}$, which is absurd. So order of a-bar is equal to order of a which is $p^m$.
Therefore $overline{a}$ is an element of maximum order in $overline{G}$.



By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is K? How are we even defining K in the steps below?]



Let K be the pullback of $overline{K}$ under the natural homomorphism from G to G-bar.



We claim that $langle a rangle cap K = {e}$. For if $x in langle overline{a} rangle cap overline{K} = {e} = langle b rangle$ and $x in langle a rangle cap langle b rangle = {e}$.



It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = <a>K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.



I am currently teaching myself abstract algebra and real analysis and this proof has be confused for a while now. I apologize for the length of the post, but I could not think of any other way to convey my doubts in any concise manner.







abstract-algebra abelian-groups






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited May 8 '17 at 13:59









Arbuja

643830




643830










asked May 8 '17 at 13:41









Sat DSat D

423212




423212












  • $begingroup$
    Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 13:53












  • $begingroup$
    The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
    $endgroup$
    – Sat D
    May 8 '17 at 14:32










  • $begingroup$
    You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 14:41










  • $begingroup$
    See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
    $endgroup$
    – lhf
    Jan 7 at 9:35


















  • $begingroup$
    Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 13:53












  • $begingroup$
    The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
    $endgroup$
    – Sat D
    May 8 '17 at 14:32










  • $begingroup$
    You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
    $endgroup$
    – Mathematician 42
    May 8 '17 at 14:41










  • $begingroup$
    See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
    $endgroup$
    – lhf
    Jan 7 at 9:35
















$begingroup$
Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
$endgroup$
– Mathematician 42
May 8 '17 at 13:53






$begingroup$
Did you consult this proof : proofwiki.org/wiki/… ? I'm just asking because I recently encountered this as well and some steps require some thought.
$endgroup$
– Mathematician 42
May 8 '17 at 13:53














$begingroup$
The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
$endgroup$
– Sat D
May 8 '17 at 14:32




$begingroup$
The statement in the text I am using makes no mention of the product being of cyclic groups... Is that the actual case?
$endgroup$
– Sat D
May 8 '17 at 14:32












$begingroup$
You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
$endgroup$
– Mathematician 42
May 8 '17 at 14:41




$begingroup$
You can prove that as a corollary to this result.
$endgroup$
– Mathematician 42
May 8 '17 at 14:41












$begingroup$
See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
$endgroup$
– lhf
Jan 7 at 9:35




$begingroup$
See also math.stackexchange.com/questions/792528/…
$endgroup$
– lhf
Jan 7 at 9:35










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















1












$begingroup$

This is Lemma 2 Ch. 11 from : 'Gallian , Contemporary abstract algebra' leading to the fundamental theorem.




Proof: We denote $|G|$ by $p^n$ and induct on $n$. If $n = 1$, then $G = langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random $m$ for the order of $a$? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]




The induction hypothesis assumes that the lemma has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k
$. By contrast $p^m$ is the highest order of all the elements of $G$. So the only thing we can say about $m$ is that it must be smaller than or equal to $n$.




Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in $G$. [Question: How, if $|G| = p^k$ ?]




$|G|=p^n$ , not $p^k$ . The orders of all elements are $p^j$ for some $j$ depending on the element. Maximum of these $j$'s is $m$ , by definition.
We can write : $x^{p^m}= (x^{p^j})^{p^{m-j}} = e^{p^{m-j}} =e$




We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
Now among all elements of $G$, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which $b$ is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which $b$ is chosen? Why does $b^p$ lie in the set generated by $a$? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order $p$ according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies $b^p = e$ ?]




Let the order of $b$ be $p^j$. This implies : $frac{|b|}{p}=p^{j-1}$ , also $b^{p^j}=e implies (b^p)^{p^{j-1}} =e $. If there where $i<j$ for which $(b^p)^{p^{i-1}} =e $ that would contradict the fact that $j$ is the smallest integer for which $b^{p^j}=e$. So $frac{|b|}{p}=|b^p|$. We chose $b$ to be the element of smallest order not in $langle a rangle$. The order of $b^p$ is smaller so it must be in $langle a rangle$.
Further in the proof he proves that the order of $b$ must be $p$ and this means $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = {e}$.




Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in $G$.
If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]




Right, same argument as above.




By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle overline a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is $K$? How are we even defining $K$ in the steps below?]




The induction hypothesis states that the decomposition into some $ langle a' rangle times K'$ has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k$ less than $p^n$. Now the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$ does have order less than $p^n$ , so it can be decomposed this way by the assumption of the induction hypothesis for every $overline a$ and some $overline K$.




It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = langle a rangle K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.




$overline K$ consists of cosets of $langle b rangle$. The set $K$ is by definition all the elements of $G$ that are in these cosets $ in overline K $. So : $|K|=| overline K| cdot |langle b rangle|$ .
By Lagrange we have : $|G|=|overline G| cdot |langle b rangle| implies |G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle|$
( last step is because : $ overline G = langle overline a rangle overline K land langle overline a rangle cap langle overline K rangle = {e} implies | overline G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | $ )

Because it is also proven above that : $|a|=|overline a| implies |langle a rangle |=| langle overline a rangle |$ we have : $|G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle| = |langle overline a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle K |$

( last step because it is proven above that : $ langle a rangle cap langle K rangle = {e}$ ) .

We have : $|G|=|langle a rangle K|$ $ implies $ $langle a rangle K$ contains the same number of elements as $G $ $ implies $ both sets must be equal.
With this last result we conclude that all the necessary conditions for $ langle a rangle times K $ to be a valid internal direct product are fulfilled .






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$





















    0












    $begingroup$

    With regards to Question 1: No, the converse is not true. Consider the group $Z_2 times Z_2$ - it has order 4 but no element of order 4. The 'maximum m' issue revolves around cases like this.



    With regards to the 'what induction?' issue: The entire argument is an inductive one - it is a 'course-of-values' induction where one shows that, if the hypothesis is true for all sizes smaller than N, then it is true for size N. The gist of the argument here is as follows: Choose a cyclic subgroup A of maximum size m. If this is the whole group, we're done [the base case]. Otherwise, we can find another cyclic subgroup B of order p whose intersection with A is the trivial subgroup. We pick order p for B because we don't need a larger order for this argument, and we know we can find such a B for order p [not necessarily for larger orders]. Now we factor the original group by B to get a smaller group [this is our induction step] We chose B to have trivial intersection with A so that the image of A in the factor group is isomorphic with A - i.e A doesn't shrink. Since [by induction] A (or rather, a group isomorphic with A) is a factor of the smaller group, projecting back we find that A is a factor of the original group.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
      $endgroup$
      – Sat D
      May 8 '17 at 14:47











    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2271504%2fproof-of-fundamental-theorem-of-finite-abelian-groups%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    1












    $begingroup$

    This is Lemma 2 Ch. 11 from : 'Gallian , Contemporary abstract algebra' leading to the fundamental theorem.




    Proof: We denote $|G|$ by $p^n$ and induct on $n$. If $n = 1$, then $G = langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
    Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random $m$ for the order of $a$? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]




    The induction hypothesis assumes that the lemma has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k
    $. By contrast $p^m$ is the highest order of all the elements of $G$. So the only thing we can say about $m$ is that it must be smaller than or equal to $n$.




    Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in $G$. [Question: How, if $|G| = p^k$ ?]




    $|G|=p^n$ , not $p^k$ . The orders of all elements are $p^j$ for some $j$ depending on the element. Maximum of these $j$'s is $m$ , by definition.
    We can write : $x^{p^m}= (x^{p^j})^{p^{m-j}} = e^{p^{m-j}} =e$




    We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
    Now among all elements of $G$, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
    We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
    Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which $b$ is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which $b$ is chosen? Why does $b^p$ lie in the set generated by $a$? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order $p$ according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies $b^p = e$ ?]




    Let the order of $b$ be $p^j$. This implies : $frac{|b|}{p}=p^{j-1}$ , also $b^{p^j}=e implies (b^p)^{p^{j-1}} =e $. If there where $i<j$ for which $(b^p)^{p^{i-1}} =e $ that would contradict the fact that $j$ is the smallest integer for which $b^{p^j}=e$. So $frac{|b|}{p}=|b^p|$. We chose $b$ to be the element of smallest order not in $langle a rangle$. The order of $b^p$ is smaller so it must be in $langle a rangle$.
    Further in the proof he proves that the order of $b$ must be $p$ and this means $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = {e}$.




    Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in $G$.
    If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]




    Right, same argument as above.




    By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle overline a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is $K$? How are we even defining $K$ in the steps below?]




    The induction hypothesis states that the decomposition into some $ langle a' rangle times K'$ has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k$ less than $p^n$. Now the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$ does have order less than $p^n$ , so it can be decomposed this way by the assumption of the induction hypothesis for every $overline a$ and some $overline K$.




    It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = langle a rangle K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.




    $overline K$ consists of cosets of $langle b rangle$. The set $K$ is by definition all the elements of $G$ that are in these cosets $ in overline K $. So : $|K|=| overline K| cdot |langle b rangle|$ .
    By Lagrange we have : $|G|=|overline G| cdot |langle b rangle| implies |G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle|$
    ( last step is because : $ overline G = langle overline a rangle overline K land langle overline a rangle cap langle overline K rangle = {e} implies | overline G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | $ )

    Because it is also proven above that : $|a|=|overline a| implies |langle a rangle |=| langle overline a rangle |$ we have : $|G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle| = |langle overline a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle K |$

    ( last step because it is proven above that : $ langle a rangle cap langle K rangle = {e}$ ) .

    We have : $|G|=|langle a rangle K|$ $ implies $ $langle a rangle K$ contains the same number of elements as $G $ $ implies $ both sets must be equal.
    With this last result we conclude that all the necessary conditions for $ langle a rangle times K $ to be a valid internal direct product are fulfilled .






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$


















      1












      $begingroup$

      This is Lemma 2 Ch. 11 from : 'Gallian , Contemporary abstract algebra' leading to the fundamental theorem.




      Proof: We denote $|G|$ by $p^n$ and induct on $n$. If $n = 1$, then $G = langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
      Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random $m$ for the order of $a$? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]




      The induction hypothesis assumes that the lemma has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k
      $. By contrast $p^m$ is the highest order of all the elements of $G$. So the only thing we can say about $m$ is that it must be smaller than or equal to $n$.




      Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in $G$. [Question: How, if $|G| = p^k$ ?]




      $|G|=p^n$ , not $p^k$ . The orders of all elements are $p^j$ for some $j$ depending on the element. Maximum of these $j$'s is $m$ , by definition.
      We can write : $x^{p^m}= (x^{p^j})^{p^{m-j}} = e^{p^{m-j}} =e$




      We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
      Now among all elements of $G$, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
      We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
      Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which $b$ is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which $b$ is chosen? Why does $b^p$ lie in the set generated by $a$? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order $p$ according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies $b^p = e$ ?]




      Let the order of $b$ be $p^j$. This implies : $frac{|b|}{p}=p^{j-1}$ , also $b^{p^j}=e implies (b^p)^{p^{j-1}} =e $. If there where $i<j$ for which $(b^p)^{p^{i-1}} =e $ that would contradict the fact that $j$ is the smallest integer for which $b^{p^j}=e$. So $frac{|b|}{p}=|b^p|$. We chose $b$ to be the element of smallest order not in $langle a rangle$. The order of $b^p$ is smaller so it must be in $langle a rangle$.
      Further in the proof he proves that the order of $b$ must be $p$ and this means $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = {e}$.




      Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in $G$.
      If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]




      Right, same argument as above.




      By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle overline a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is $K$? How are we even defining $K$ in the steps below?]




      The induction hypothesis states that the decomposition into some $ langle a' rangle times K'$ has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k$ less than $p^n$. Now the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$ does have order less than $p^n$ , so it can be decomposed this way by the assumption of the induction hypothesis for every $overline a$ and some $overline K$.




      It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = langle a rangle K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.




      $overline K$ consists of cosets of $langle b rangle$. The set $K$ is by definition all the elements of $G$ that are in these cosets $ in overline K $. So : $|K|=| overline K| cdot |langle b rangle|$ .
      By Lagrange we have : $|G|=|overline G| cdot |langle b rangle| implies |G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle|$
      ( last step is because : $ overline G = langle overline a rangle overline K land langle overline a rangle cap langle overline K rangle = {e} implies | overline G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | $ )

      Because it is also proven above that : $|a|=|overline a| implies |langle a rangle |=| langle overline a rangle |$ we have : $|G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle| = |langle overline a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle K |$

      ( last step because it is proven above that : $ langle a rangle cap langle K rangle = {e}$ ) .

      We have : $|G|=|langle a rangle K|$ $ implies $ $langle a rangle K$ contains the same number of elements as $G $ $ implies $ both sets must be equal.
      With this last result we conclude that all the necessary conditions for $ langle a rangle times K $ to be a valid internal direct product are fulfilled .






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$
















        1












        1








        1





        $begingroup$

        This is Lemma 2 Ch. 11 from : 'Gallian , Contemporary abstract algebra' leading to the fundamental theorem.




        Proof: We denote $|G|$ by $p^n$ and induct on $n$. If $n = 1$, then $G = langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
        Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random $m$ for the order of $a$? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]




        The induction hypothesis assumes that the lemma has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k
        $. By contrast $p^m$ is the highest order of all the elements of $G$. So the only thing we can say about $m$ is that it must be smaller than or equal to $n$.




        Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in $G$. [Question: How, if $|G| = p^k$ ?]




        $|G|=p^n$ , not $p^k$ . The orders of all elements are $p^j$ for some $j$ depending on the element. Maximum of these $j$'s is $m$ , by definition.
        We can write : $x^{p^m}= (x^{p^j})^{p^{m-j}} = e^{p^{m-j}} =e$




        We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
        Now among all elements of $G$, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
        We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
        Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which $b$ is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which $b$ is chosen? Why does $b^p$ lie in the set generated by $a$? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order $p$ according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies $b^p = e$ ?]




        Let the order of $b$ be $p^j$. This implies : $frac{|b|}{p}=p^{j-1}$ , also $b^{p^j}=e implies (b^p)^{p^{j-1}} =e $. If there where $i<j$ for which $(b^p)^{p^{i-1}} =e $ that would contradict the fact that $j$ is the smallest integer for which $b^{p^j}=e$. So $frac{|b|}{p}=|b^p|$. We chose $b$ to be the element of smallest order not in $langle a rangle$. The order of $b^p$ is smaller so it must be in $langle a rangle$.
        Further in the proof he proves that the order of $b$ must be $p$ and this means $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = {e}$.




        Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in $G$.
        If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]




        Right, same argument as above.




        By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle overline a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is $K$? How are we even defining $K$ in the steps below?]




        The induction hypothesis states that the decomposition into some $ langle a' rangle times K'$ has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k$ less than $p^n$. Now the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$ does have order less than $p^n$ , so it can be decomposed this way by the assumption of the induction hypothesis for every $overline a$ and some $overline K$.




        It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = langle a rangle K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.




        $overline K$ consists of cosets of $langle b rangle$. The set $K$ is by definition all the elements of $G$ that are in these cosets $ in overline K $. So : $|K|=| overline K| cdot |langle b rangle|$ .
        By Lagrange we have : $|G|=|overline G| cdot |langle b rangle| implies |G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle|$
        ( last step is because : $ overline G = langle overline a rangle overline K land langle overline a rangle cap langle overline K rangle = {e} implies | overline G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | $ )

        Because it is also proven above that : $|a|=|overline a| implies |langle a rangle |=| langle overline a rangle |$ we have : $|G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle| = |langle overline a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle K |$

        ( last step because it is proven above that : $ langle a rangle cap langle K rangle = {e}$ ) .

        We have : $|G|=|langle a rangle K|$ $ implies $ $langle a rangle K$ contains the same number of elements as $G $ $ implies $ both sets must be equal.
        With this last result we conclude that all the necessary conditions for $ langle a rangle times K $ to be a valid internal direct product are fulfilled .






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$



        This is Lemma 2 Ch. 11 from : 'Gallian , Contemporary abstract algebra' leading to the fundamental theorem.




        Proof: We denote $|G|$ by $p^n$ and induct on $n$. If $n = 1$, then $G = langle a rangle times langle e rangle$. Now assume that the statement is true for all Abelian groups of order $p^k$, where $k < n$.
        Among all elements of G, choose $a$ of maximum order $p^m$. [Question: Why are we picking any random $m$ for the order of $a$? For Abelian groups, isn't the converse of Lagrange always true? So shouldn't the element a have order $p^{k-1}$?]




        The induction hypothesis assumes that the lemma has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k
        $. By contrast $p^m$ is the highest order of all the elements of $G$. So the only thing we can say about $m$ is that it must be smaller than or equal to $n$.




        Then $x^{p^m} = e$ for all $x$ in $G$. [Question: How, if $|G| = p^k$ ?]




        $|G|=p^n$ , not $p^k$ . The orders of all elements are $p^j$ for some $j$ depending on the element. Maximum of these $j$'s is $m$ , by definition.
        We can write : $x^{p^m}= (x^{p^j})^{p^{m-j}} = e^{p^{m-j}} =e$




        We assume that $G neq langle a rangle$, as there would be nothing left to prove then.
        Now among all elements of $G$, choose $b$ of smallest order such does $b notin langle a rangle$.
        We claim that $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = e$
        Since $|b^p| = |b|/p$, we know that $b^p in langle a rangle$ by the manner in which $b$ is chosen. [Question: What does he mean by the manner in which $b$ is chosen? Why does $b^p$ lie in the set generated by $a$? Is it because the group with the minimum order has to have order $p$ according to Lagrange and this straightaway implies $b^p = e$ ?]




        Let the order of $b$ be $p^j$. This implies : $frac{|b|}{p}=p^{j-1}$ , also $b^{p^j}=e implies (b^p)^{p^{j-1}} =e $. If there where $i<j$ for which $(b^p)^{p^{i-1}} =e $ that would contradict the fact that $j$ is the smallest integer for which $b^{p^j}=e$. So $frac{|b|}{p}=|b^p|$. We chose $b$ to be the element of smallest order not in $langle a rangle$. The order of $b^p$ is smaller so it must be in $langle a rangle$.
        Further in the proof he proves that the order of $b$ must be $p$ and this means $langle b rangle cap langle a rangle = {e}$.




        Consider the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$. Let $overline{x}=xlangle b rangle$ in $G$.
        If $|overline{a}| < |a| = p^m$, then $overline{a}^{p^{m-1}} = overline{e}$. [Question: here we have picked $p^{m-1}$ just as any arbitrary number less than $p^m$, but still a power of $p$, right?]




        Right, same argument as above.




        By induction, we know that $overline{G} = langle overline a rangle times overline{K}$. [Question: ??? What induction? What is the basis of this step? What even is $K$? How are we even defining $K$ in the steps below?]




        The induction hypothesis states that the decomposition into some $ langle a' rangle times K'$ has already been proven for all groups of order $p^k$ less than $p^n$. Now the factor group $overline{G} = G/langle b rangle$ does have order less than $p^n$ , so it can be decomposed this way by the assumption of the induction hypothesis for every $overline a$ and some $overline K$.




        It now follows from an order argument (???) that $G = langle a rangle K$, and therefore $G = langle a rangle times K$.




        $overline K$ consists of cosets of $langle b rangle$. The set $K$ is by definition all the elements of $G$ that are in these cosets $ in overline K $. So : $|K|=| overline K| cdot |langle b rangle|$ .
        By Lagrange we have : $|G|=|overline G| cdot |langle b rangle| implies |G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle|$
        ( last step is because : $ overline G = langle overline a rangle overline K land langle overline a rangle cap langle overline K rangle = {e} implies | overline G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | $ )

        Because it is also proven above that : $|a|=|overline a| implies |langle a rangle |=| langle overline a rangle |$ we have : $|G|= |langle overline a rangle | cdot | overline K | cdot |langle b rangle| = |langle overline a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle | cdot | K | = |langle a rangle K |$

        ( last step because it is proven above that : $ langle a rangle cap langle K rangle = {e}$ ) .

        We have : $|G|=|langle a rangle K|$ $ implies $ $langle a rangle K$ contains the same number of elements as $G $ $ implies $ both sets must be equal.
        With this last result we conclude that all the necessary conditions for $ langle a rangle times K $ to be a valid internal direct product are fulfilled .







        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited Sep 9 '17 at 8:52

























        answered Sep 8 '17 at 13:49









        Rutger MoodyRutger Moody

        1,4901918




        1,4901918























            0












            $begingroup$

            With regards to Question 1: No, the converse is not true. Consider the group $Z_2 times Z_2$ - it has order 4 but no element of order 4. The 'maximum m' issue revolves around cases like this.



            With regards to the 'what induction?' issue: The entire argument is an inductive one - it is a 'course-of-values' induction where one shows that, if the hypothesis is true for all sizes smaller than N, then it is true for size N. The gist of the argument here is as follows: Choose a cyclic subgroup A of maximum size m. If this is the whole group, we're done [the base case]. Otherwise, we can find another cyclic subgroup B of order p whose intersection with A is the trivial subgroup. We pick order p for B because we don't need a larger order for this argument, and we know we can find such a B for order p [not necessarily for larger orders]. Now we factor the original group by B to get a smaller group [this is our induction step] We chose B to have trivial intersection with A so that the image of A in the factor group is isomorphic with A - i.e A doesn't shrink. Since [by induction] A (or rather, a group isomorphic with A) is a factor of the smaller group, projecting back we find that A is a factor of the original group.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













            • $begingroup$
              Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
              $endgroup$
              – Sat D
              May 8 '17 at 14:47
















            0












            $begingroup$

            With regards to Question 1: No, the converse is not true. Consider the group $Z_2 times Z_2$ - it has order 4 but no element of order 4. The 'maximum m' issue revolves around cases like this.



            With regards to the 'what induction?' issue: The entire argument is an inductive one - it is a 'course-of-values' induction where one shows that, if the hypothesis is true for all sizes smaller than N, then it is true for size N. The gist of the argument here is as follows: Choose a cyclic subgroup A of maximum size m. If this is the whole group, we're done [the base case]. Otherwise, we can find another cyclic subgroup B of order p whose intersection with A is the trivial subgroup. We pick order p for B because we don't need a larger order for this argument, and we know we can find such a B for order p [not necessarily for larger orders]. Now we factor the original group by B to get a smaller group [this is our induction step] We chose B to have trivial intersection with A so that the image of A in the factor group is isomorphic with A - i.e A doesn't shrink. Since [by induction] A (or rather, a group isomorphic with A) is a factor of the smaller group, projecting back we find that A is a factor of the original group.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













            • $begingroup$
              Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
              $endgroup$
              – Sat D
              May 8 '17 at 14:47














            0












            0








            0





            $begingroup$

            With regards to Question 1: No, the converse is not true. Consider the group $Z_2 times Z_2$ - it has order 4 but no element of order 4. The 'maximum m' issue revolves around cases like this.



            With regards to the 'what induction?' issue: The entire argument is an inductive one - it is a 'course-of-values' induction where one shows that, if the hypothesis is true for all sizes smaller than N, then it is true for size N. The gist of the argument here is as follows: Choose a cyclic subgroup A of maximum size m. If this is the whole group, we're done [the base case]. Otherwise, we can find another cyclic subgroup B of order p whose intersection with A is the trivial subgroup. We pick order p for B because we don't need a larger order for this argument, and we know we can find such a B for order p [not necessarily for larger orders]. Now we factor the original group by B to get a smaller group [this is our induction step] We chose B to have trivial intersection with A so that the image of A in the factor group is isomorphic with A - i.e A doesn't shrink. Since [by induction] A (or rather, a group isomorphic with A) is a factor of the smaller group, projecting back we find that A is a factor of the original group.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$



            With regards to Question 1: No, the converse is not true. Consider the group $Z_2 times Z_2$ - it has order 4 but no element of order 4. The 'maximum m' issue revolves around cases like this.



            With regards to the 'what induction?' issue: The entire argument is an inductive one - it is a 'course-of-values' induction where one shows that, if the hypothesis is true for all sizes smaller than N, then it is true for size N. The gist of the argument here is as follows: Choose a cyclic subgroup A of maximum size m. If this is the whole group, we're done [the base case]. Otherwise, we can find another cyclic subgroup B of order p whose intersection with A is the trivial subgroup. We pick order p for B because we don't need a larger order for this argument, and we know we can find such a B for order p [not necessarily for larger orders]. Now we factor the original group by B to get a smaller group [this is our induction step] We chose B to have trivial intersection with A so that the image of A in the factor group is isomorphic with A - i.e A doesn't shrink. Since [by induction] A (or rather, a group isomorphic with A) is a factor of the smaller group, projecting back we find that A is a factor of the original group.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered May 8 '17 at 14:01









            PMarPMar

            1




            1












            • $begingroup$
              Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
              $endgroup$
              – Sat D
              May 8 '17 at 14:47


















            • $begingroup$
              Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
              $endgroup$
              – Sat D
              May 8 '17 at 14:47
















            $begingroup$
            Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
            $endgroup$
            – Sat D
            May 8 '17 at 14:47




            $begingroup$
            Why does he say that b^p lies in <a>, however? Does it stem from the fact that b^p is a smaller cyclic group than b, and that contradicts the way we chose b?
            $endgroup$
            – Sat D
            May 8 '17 at 14:47


















            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2271504%2fproof-of-fundamental-theorem-of-finite-abelian-groups%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            'app-layout' is not a known element: how to share Component with different Modules

            android studio warns about leanback feature tag usage required on manifest while using Unity exported app?

            WPF add header to Image with URL pettitions [duplicate]