Does the category $mathsf{DL}$ of bounded distributive lattices have (filtered) colimits?












1














How do I show that the category $mathsf{DL}$ of bounded distributive lattices and monotone maps has (filtered) colimits? I guess we have an adjunction
$$
F dashv U : mathsf{DL} to mathsf{Set}.
$$

Then $U$ preserves limits and $F$ preserves colimits. Can we deduce from this that $mathsf{DL}$ has (filtered) colimits, and if so, how?










share|cite|improve this question



























    1














    How do I show that the category $mathsf{DL}$ of bounded distributive lattices and monotone maps has (filtered) colimits? I guess we have an adjunction
    $$
    F dashv U : mathsf{DL} to mathsf{Set}.
    $$

    Then $U$ preserves limits and $F$ preserves colimits. Can we deduce from this that $mathsf{DL}$ has (filtered) colimits, and if so, how?










    share|cite|improve this question

























      1












      1








      1







      How do I show that the category $mathsf{DL}$ of bounded distributive lattices and monotone maps has (filtered) colimits? I guess we have an adjunction
      $$
      F dashv U : mathsf{DL} to mathsf{Set}.
      $$

      Then $U$ preserves limits and $F$ preserves colimits. Can we deduce from this that $mathsf{DL}$ has (filtered) colimits, and if so, how?










      share|cite|improve this question













      How do I show that the category $mathsf{DL}$ of bounded distributive lattices and monotone maps has (filtered) colimits? I guess we have an adjunction
      $$
      F dashv U : mathsf{DL} to mathsf{Set}.
      $$

      Then $U$ preserves limits and $F$ preserves colimits. Can we deduce from this that $mathsf{DL}$ has (filtered) colimits, and if so, how?







      category-theory






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Nov 19 '18 at 23:35









      Math Student 020

      946616




      946616






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          2














          The below assumes that your morphisms of bounded distributive lattices are maps preserving meets, joins, top, and bottom.



          Your adjunction, like any free-forgetful adjunction between categories of models of an algebraic theory, is monadic. In particular, it creates reflexive coequalizers. This tells us, essentially, that we can construct unique bounded distributive lattice (bdl) structures on the quotient set of a bdl by a congruence: an equivalence relation closed under the lattice operations. Now, the usual construction of colimits from coproducts and coequalizers actually uses only reflexive coequalizers. Thus to give all colimits of bdls it suffices to give their coproducts. And this is easy, in terms of generators and relations: a presentation of the coproduct of a family of bdls is just the disjoint union of presentations of each bdl in the family. Of course, as with free products of groups, the actual elements of such a coproduct can be tricky to get a handle on. But it certainly exists!



          Filtered colimits are even easier: the forgetful functor, again, creates them. This isn't a property of general monads, but of those corresponding to algebraic theories in particular. The point is that the filtered colimits of the underlying sets of some filtered family $L_i$ of bdls has, again, a unique bdl structure making the inclusion maps into homomorphisms. It's given simply by $[a_i]vee [b_i]=[a_ivee b_i]$, $0=[0_i]$ etc. The filteredness serves to show that these formulae define all possible meets and joins in a well defined way and that the resulting operations are distributive.



          All of the above holds for the category of models of any finitary algebraic theory, which covers most familiar categories of algebra with exceptions like fields (axioms can only be equations), posets (there are only operations, no relations), and complete lattices (operations must be of finite arity.)






          share|cite|improve this answer

















          • 1




            This is very helpful, thanks!
            – Math Student 020
            Nov 20 '18 at 1:53











          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














          draft saved

          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3005692%2fdoes-the-category-mathsfdl-of-bounded-distributive-lattices-have-filtered%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes









          2














          The below assumes that your morphisms of bounded distributive lattices are maps preserving meets, joins, top, and bottom.



          Your adjunction, like any free-forgetful adjunction between categories of models of an algebraic theory, is monadic. In particular, it creates reflexive coequalizers. This tells us, essentially, that we can construct unique bounded distributive lattice (bdl) structures on the quotient set of a bdl by a congruence: an equivalence relation closed under the lattice operations. Now, the usual construction of colimits from coproducts and coequalizers actually uses only reflexive coequalizers. Thus to give all colimits of bdls it suffices to give their coproducts. And this is easy, in terms of generators and relations: a presentation of the coproduct of a family of bdls is just the disjoint union of presentations of each bdl in the family. Of course, as with free products of groups, the actual elements of such a coproduct can be tricky to get a handle on. But it certainly exists!



          Filtered colimits are even easier: the forgetful functor, again, creates them. This isn't a property of general monads, but of those corresponding to algebraic theories in particular. The point is that the filtered colimits of the underlying sets of some filtered family $L_i$ of bdls has, again, a unique bdl structure making the inclusion maps into homomorphisms. It's given simply by $[a_i]vee [b_i]=[a_ivee b_i]$, $0=[0_i]$ etc. The filteredness serves to show that these formulae define all possible meets and joins in a well defined way and that the resulting operations are distributive.



          All of the above holds for the category of models of any finitary algebraic theory, which covers most familiar categories of algebra with exceptions like fields (axioms can only be equations), posets (there are only operations, no relations), and complete lattices (operations must be of finite arity.)






          share|cite|improve this answer

















          • 1




            This is very helpful, thanks!
            – Math Student 020
            Nov 20 '18 at 1:53
















          2














          The below assumes that your morphisms of bounded distributive lattices are maps preserving meets, joins, top, and bottom.



          Your adjunction, like any free-forgetful adjunction between categories of models of an algebraic theory, is monadic. In particular, it creates reflexive coequalizers. This tells us, essentially, that we can construct unique bounded distributive lattice (bdl) structures on the quotient set of a bdl by a congruence: an equivalence relation closed under the lattice operations. Now, the usual construction of colimits from coproducts and coequalizers actually uses only reflexive coequalizers. Thus to give all colimits of bdls it suffices to give their coproducts. And this is easy, in terms of generators and relations: a presentation of the coproduct of a family of bdls is just the disjoint union of presentations of each bdl in the family. Of course, as with free products of groups, the actual elements of such a coproduct can be tricky to get a handle on. But it certainly exists!



          Filtered colimits are even easier: the forgetful functor, again, creates them. This isn't a property of general monads, but of those corresponding to algebraic theories in particular. The point is that the filtered colimits of the underlying sets of some filtered family $L_i$ of bdls has, again, a unique bdl structure making the inclusion maps into homomorphisms. It's given simply by $[a_i]vee [b_i]=[a_ivee b_i]$, $0=[0_i]$ etc. The filteredness serves to show that these formulae define all possible meets and joins in a well defined way and that the resulting operations are distributive.



          All of the above holds for the category of models of any finitary algebraic theory, which covers most familiar categories of algebra with exceptions like fields (axioms can only be equations), posets (there are only operations, no relations), and complete lattices (operations must be of finite arity.)






          share|cite|improve this answer

















          • 1




            This is very helpful, thanks!
            – Math Student 020
            Nov 20 '18 at 1:53














          2












          2








          2






          The below assumes that your morphisms of bounded distributive lattices are maps preserving meets, joins, top, and bottom.



          Your adjunction, like any free-forgetful adjunction between categories of models of an algebraic theory, is monadic. In particular, it creates reflexive coequalizers. This tells us, essentially, that we can construct unique bounded distributive lattice (bdl) structures on the quotient set of a bdl by a congruence: an equivalence relation closed under the lattice operations. Now, the usual construction of colimits from coproducts and coequalizers actually uses only reflexive coequalizers. Thus to give all colimits of bdls it suffices to give their coproducts. And this is easy, in terms of generators and relations: a presentation of the coproduct of a family of bdls is just the disjoint union of presentations of each bdl in the family. Of course, as with free products of groups, the actual elements of such a coproduct can be tricky to get a handle on. But it certainly exists!



          Filtered colimits are even easier: the forgetful functor, again, creates them. This isn't a property of general monads, but of those corresponding to algebraic theories in particular. The point is that the filtered colimits of the underlying sets of some filtered family $L_i$ of bdls has, again, a unique bdl structure making the inclusion maps into homomorphisms. It's given simply by $[a_i]vee [b_i]=[a_ivee b_i]$, $0=[0_i]$ etc. The filteredness serves to show that these formulae define all possible meets and joins in a well defined way and that the resulting operations are distributive.



          All of the above holds for the category of models of any finitary algebraic theory, which covers most familiar categories of algebra with exceptions like fields (axioms can only be equations), posets (there are only operations, no relations), and complete lattices (operations must be of finite arity.)






          share|cite|improve this answer












          The below assumes that your morphisms of bounded distributive lattices are maps preserving meets, joins, top, and bottom.



          Your adjunction, like any free-forgetful adjunction between categories of models of an algebraic theory, is monadic. In particular, it creates reflexive coequalizers. This tells us, essentially, that we can construct unique bounded distributive lattice (bdl) structures on the quotient set of a bdl by a congruence: an equivalence relation closed under the lattice operations. Now, the usual construction of colimits from coproducts and coequalizers actually uses only reflexive coequalizers. Thus to give all colimits of bdls it suffices to give their coproducts. And this is easy, in terms of generators and relations: a presentation of the coproduct of a family of bdls is just the disjoint union of presentations of each bdl in the family. Of course, as with free products of groups, the actual elements of such a coproduct can be tricky to get a handle on. But it certainly exists!



          Filtered colimits are even easier: the forgetful functor, again, creates them. This isn't a property of general monads, but of those corresponding to algebraic theories in particular. The point is that the filtered colimits of the underlying sets of some filtered family $L_i$ of bdls has, again, a unique bdl structure making the inclusion maps into homomorphisms. It's given simply by $[a_i]vee [b_i]=[a_ivee b_i]$, $0=[0_i]$ etc. The filteredness serves to show that these formulae define all possible meets and joins in a well defined way and that the resulting operations are distributive.



          All of the above holds for the category of models of any finitary algebraic theory, which covers most familiar categories of algebra with exceptions like fields (axioms can only be equations), posets (there are only operations, no relations), and complete lattices (operations must be of finite arity.)







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Nov 20 '18 at 1:27









          Kevin Carlson

          32.5k23271




          32.5k23271








          • 1




            This is very helpful, thanks!
            – Math Student 020
            Nov 20 '18 at 1:53














          • 1




            This is very helpful, thanks!
            – Math Student 020
            Nov 20 '18 at 1:53








          1




          1




          This is very helpful, thanks!
          – Math Student 020
          Nov 20 '18 at 1:53




          This is very helpful, thanks!
          – Math Student 020
          Nov 20 '18 at 1:53


















          draft saved

          draft discarded




















































          Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





          Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


          Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


          • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

          But avoid



          • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

          • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


          To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3005692%2fdoes-the-category-mathsfdl-of-bounded-distributive-lattices-have-filtered%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          Can a sorcerer learn a 5th-level spell early by creating spell slots using the Font of Magic feature?

          Does disintegrating a polymorphed enemy still kill it after the 2018 errata?

          A Topological Invariant for $pi_3(U(n))$