Fermat's Last Theorem solved through induction on $z$, not on $n$












-3












$begingroup$



Assume that we have shown a proof for the case $z=1$ and $z=2$ for $x^n +y^n = z^n$.



Can we say that via mathematical induction on $z$ that this is now true for all integers $z$ for $n>2?$











share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
    $endgroup$
    – Dietrich Burde
    Jan 16 at 14:36












  • $begingroup$
    Can you prove it for $z=1?$
    $endgroup$
    – Mohammad Zuhair Khan
    Jan 16 at 14:39










  • $begingroup$
    We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter
    Jan 16 at 23:24
















-3












$begingroup$



Assume that we have shown a proof for the case $z=1$ and $z=2$ for $x^n +y^n = z^n$.



Can we say that via mathematical induction on $z$ that this is now true for all integers $z$ for $n>2?$











share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
    $endgroup$
    – Dietrich Burde
    Jan 16 at 14:36












  • $begingroup$
    Can you prove it for $z=1?$
    $endgroup$
    – Mohammad Zuhair Khan
    Jan 16 at 14:39










  • $begingroup$
    We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter
    Jan 16 at 23:24














-3












-3








-3





$begingroup$



Assume that we have shown a proof for the case $z=1$ and $z=2$ for $x^n +y^n = z^n$.



Can we say that via mathematical induction on $z$ that this is now true for all integers $z$ for $n>2?$











share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$





Assume that we have shown a proof for the case $z=1$ and $z=2$ for $x^n +y^n = z^n$.



Can we say that via mathematical induction on $z$ that this is now true for all integers $z$ for $n>2?$








number-theory






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jan 16 at 15:26









Mohammad Zuhair Khan

1,5852625




1,5852625










asked Jan 16 at 14:28









azdinazdin

34




34








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
    $endgroup$
    – Dietrich Burde
    Jan 16 at 14:36












  • $begingroup$
    Can you prove it for $z=1?$
    $endgroup$
    – Mohammad Zuhair Khan
    Jan 16 at 14:39










  • $begingroup$
    We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter
    Jan 16 at 23:24














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
    $endgroup$
    – Dietrich Burde
    Jan 16 at 14:36












  • $begingroup$
    Can you prove it for $z=1?$
    $endgroup$
    – Mohammad Zuhair Khan
    Jan 16 at 14:39










  • $begingroup$
    We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter
    Jan 16 at 23:24








2




2




$begingroup$
How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
$endgroup$
– Dietrich Burde
Jan 16 at 14:36






$begingroup$
How would you do the induction step? Clearly the base case $x^n+y^n=1$ is easy.
$endgroup$
– Dietrich Burde
Jan 16 at 14:36














$begingroup$
Can you prove it for $z=1?$
$endgroup$
– Mohammad Zuhair Khan
Jan 16 at 14:39




$begingroup$
Can you prove it for $z=1?$
$endgroup$
– Mohammad Zuhair Khan
Jan 16 at 14:39












$begingroup$
We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
$endgroup$
– Peter
Jan 16 at 23:24




$begingroup$
We can safely assume that if Fermat's last theorem could be solved via induction on $z$ , the theorem would have been proven long before Andrew Wiles's proof. Concluding from $z=1$ and $z=2$ to all $z$ is of course not possible : Simple example : $1$ and $2$ are divisors of $4$. Does that mean that all positive integers are divisors of $4$ ? Of course, no.
$endgroup$
– Peter
Jan 16 at 23:24










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















2












$begingroup$

I'm afraid this isn't quite how proof by induction works.



Call $P$ whatever we're proving about $z$. We can't simply say "$P$ is true for $z=1$ and $z=2$, therefore it's true for all $z>2$". (For example, "$z<3$" is true for both of them but false for $z>2$.)



To prove $P$ by induction we have to show that $P$ being true for one case forces it to be true for the next. Then we say 'Well it's true for $z=1$ so it must be true for $z=2$, so it must be true for $z=3$, so . . . " and let this count its way through all the remaining positive integers. But we've not got infinitely long in which to do the counting, so we compress that into " so by induction, it's true for all $zgeq 1$".



The key point is that each case must prove the next one, so there's a chain all the way up from a case that we already know to be true.



So I'm afraid your proof needs to do rather more.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    +1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 15:37










  • $begingroup$
    @NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Jan 16 at 15:40



















0












$begingroup$

Mathematical induction isn't "It works for $1$, it works for $2$, so it always works." You have to prove that the statement in question being true for $k$ implies that it is also true for $k+1$ - for any value of $k$ (or an equivalent variant of this).



What you seem to be doing is assuming that the induction step is given as proved already, which isn't the case - usually in fact this is precisely the nontrivial part of a proof by induction.



So no, you cannot say anything about FLT.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 16 at 23:10












  • $begingroup$
    @azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 23:45












  • $begingroup$
    Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 9:06










  • $begingroup$
    @azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 17 at 16:18












  • $begingroup$
    I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 23:25











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3075801%2ffermats-last-theorem-solved-through-induction-on-z-not-on-n%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes








2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









2












$begingroup$

I'm afraid this isn't quite how proof by induction works.



Call $P$ whatever we're proving about $z$. We can't simply say "$P$ is true for $z=1$ and $z=2$, therefore it's true for all $z>2$". (For example, "$z<3$" is true for both of them but false for $z>2$.)



To prove $P$ by induction we have to show that $P$ being true for one case forces it to be true for the next. Then we say 'Well it's true for $z=1$ so it must be true for $z=2$, so it must be true for $z=3$, so . . . " and let this count its way through all the remaining positive integers. But we've not got infinitely long in which to do the counting, so we compress that into " so by induction, it's true for all $zgeq 1$".



The key point is that each case must prove the next one, so there's a chain all the way up from a case that we already know to be true.



So I'm afraid your proof needs to do rather more.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    +1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 15:37










  • $begingroup$
    @NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Jan 16 at 15:40
















2












$begingroup$

I'm afraid this isn't quite how proof by induction works.



Call $P$ whatever we're proving about $z$. We can't simply say "$P$ is true for $z=1$ and $z=2$, therefore it's true for all $z>2$". (For example, "$z<3$" is true for both of them but false for $z>2$.)



To prove $P$ by induction we have to show that $P$ being true for one case forces it to be true for the next. Then we say 'Well it's true for $z=1$ so it must be true for $z=2$, so it must be true for $z=3$, so . . . " and let this count its way through all the remaining positive integers. But we've not got infinitely long in which to do the counting, so we compress that into " so by induction, it's true for all $zgeq 1$".



The key point is that each case must prove the next one, so there's a chain all the way up from a case that we already know to be true.



So I'm afraid your proof needs to do rather more.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    +1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 15:37










  • $begingroup$
    @NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Jan 16 at 15:40














2












2








2





$begingroup$

I'm afraid this isn't quite how proof by induction works.



Call $P$ whatever we're proving about $z$. We can't simply say "$P$ is true for $z=1$ and $z=2$, therefore it's true for all $z>2$". (For example, "$z<3$" is true for both of them but false for $z>2$.)



To prove $P$ by induction we have to show that $P$ being true for one case forces it to be true for the next. Then we say 'Well it's true for $z=1$ so it must be true for $z=2$, so it must be true for $z=3$, so . . . " and let this count its way through all the remaining positive integers. But we've not got infinitely long in which to do the counting, so we compress that into " so by induction, it's true for all $zgeq 1$".



The key point is that each case must prove the next one, so there's a chain all the way up from a case that we already know to be true.



So I'm afraid your proof needs to do rather more.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



I'm afraid this isn't quite how proof by induction works.



Call $P$ whatever we're proving about $z$. We can't simply say "$P$ is true for $z=1$ and $z=2$, therefore it's true for all $z>2$". (For example, "$z<3$" is true for both of them but false for $z>2$.)



To prove $P$ by induction we have to show that $P$ being true for one case forces it to be true for the next. Then we say 'Well it's true for $z=1$ so it must be true for $z=2$, so it must be true for $z=3$, so . . . " and let this count its way through all the remaining positive integers. But we've not got infinitely long in which to do the counting, so we compress that into " so by induction, it's true for all $zgeq 1$".



The key point is that each case must prove the next one, so there's a chain all the way up from a case that we already know to be true.



So I'm afraid your proof needs to do rather more.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Jan 16 at 15:36









timtfjtimtfj

2,448420




2,448420












  • $begingroup$
    +1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 15:37










  • $begingroup$
    @NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Jan 16 at 15:40


















  • $begingroup$
    +1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 15:37










  • $begingroup$
    @NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
    $endgroup$
    – timtfj
    Jan 16 at 15:40
















$begingroup$
+1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 16 at 15:37




$begingroup$
+1, although "this isn't quite how proof by induction works" is putting it rather mildly ...
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 16 at 15:37












$begingroup$
@NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
$endgroup$
– timtfj
Jan 16 at 15:40




$begingroup$
@NoahSchweber Ithink "do rather more" is mild too given how much effort Andrew Wiles had to put in!
$endgroup$
– timtfj
Jan 16 at 15:40











0












$begingroup$

Mathematical induction isn't "It works for $1$, it works for $2$, so it always works." You have to prove that the statement in question being true for $k$ implies that it is also true for $k+1$ - for any value of $k$ (or an equivalent variant of this).



What you seem to be doing is assuming that the induction step is given as proved already, which isn't the case - usually in fact this is precisely the nontrivial part of a proof by induction.



So no, you cannot say anything about FLT.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 16 at 23:10












  • $begingroup$
    @azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 23:45












  • $begingroup$
    Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 9:06










  • $begingroup$
    @azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 17 at 16:18












  • $begingroup$
    I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 23:25
















0












$begingroup$

Mathematical induction isn't "It works for $1$, it works for $2$, so it always works." You have to prove that the statement in question being true for $k$ implies that it is also true for $k+1$ - for any value of $k$ (or an equivalent variant of this).



What you seem to be doing is assuming that the induction step is given as proved already, which isn't the case - usually in fact this is precisely the nontrivial part of a proof by induction.



So no, you cannot say anything about FLT.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 16 at 23:10












  • $begingroup$
    @azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 23:45












  • $begingroup$
    Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 9:06










  • $begingroup$
    @azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 17 at 16:18












  • $begingroup$
    I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 23:25














0












0








0





$begingroup$

Mathematical induction isn't "It works for $1$, it works for $2$, so it always works." You have to prove that the statement in question being true for $k$ implies that it is also true for $k+1$ - for any value of $k$ (or an equivalent variant of this).



What you seem to be doing is assuming that the induction step is given as proved already, which isn't the case - usually in fact this is precisely the nontrivial part of a proof by induction.



So no, you cannot say anything about FLT.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



Mathematical induction isn't "It works for $1$, it works for $2$, so it always works." You have to prove that the statement in question being true for $k$ implies that it is also true for $k+1$ - for any value of $k$ (or an equivalent variant of this).



What you seem to be doing is assuming that the induction step is given as proved already, which isn't the case - usually in fact this is precisely the nontrivial part of a proof by induction.



So no, you cannot say anything about FLT.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Jan 16 at 15:37









Noah SchweberNoah Schweber

125k10150287




125k10150287












  • $begingroup$
    Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 16 at 23:10












  • $begingroup$
    @azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 23:45












  • $begingroup$
    Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 9:06










  • $begingroup$
    @azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 17 at 16:18












  • $begingroup$
    I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 23:25


















  • $begingroup$
    Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 16 at 23:10












  • $begingroup$
    @azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 16 at 23:45












  • $begingroup$
    Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 9:06










  • $begingroup$
    @azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Jan 17 at 16:18












  • $begingroup$
    I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
    $endgroup$
    – azdin
    Jan 17 at 23:25
















$begingroup$
Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 16 at 23:10






$begingroup$
Case z=1 gives 1^n +1^n /= 1^n , 1^n+2^n /=1^n, 2^n+3^n /= 1^n FLT is true for z=1 whatever the value for n and x, y integers. This is the basis step.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 16 at 23:10














$begingroup$
@azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 16 at 23:45






$begingroup$
@azdin And the induction step is ... what, precisely? Wishful thinking?
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 16 at 23:45














$begingroup$
Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 17 at 9:06




$begingroup$
Induction step: We assume FLT is true until z=(p-1) and we must proove that FLT is true for z=p. The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 17 at 9:06












$begingroup$
@azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 17 at 16:18






$begingroup$
@azdin "... and we must proove ..." yes, you must prove. Having not actually done that, you cannot say that FLT is proved. "The case z=(p-1) implies the case z=p." - how do you know that?
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Jan 17 at 16:18














$begingroup$
I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 17 at 23:25




$begingroup$
I can say that FLT is proved because I have done it . I demonstrate that the case z=(p-1) implies z=p . I will send the proof in the next post in order to be reviewed by mathematicians and followers.
$endgroup$
– azdin
Jan 17 at 23:25


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3075801%2ffermats-last-theorem-solved-through-induction-on-z-not-on-n%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Can a sorcerer learn a 5th-level spell early by creating spell slots using the Font of Magic feature?

Does disintegrating a polymorphed enemy still kill it after the 2018 errata?

A Topological Invariant for $pi_3(U(n))$