If $x_n$ is a 0,1 sequence such that $text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$, then any 0,1 sequence $y_n supset x_n$ has...












1












$begingroup$


I am working through this post from Terry Tao's blog.



Problem: Prove that if a binary (i.e. consisting of $0$ and $1$, or $top$ and $bot$) sequence $x_n$ is such that $text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$, then any sequence $y_n$ containing $x_n$ has $text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$.



My attempt at a proof. We know the following facts regarding $text{p-lim}$:




  • homomorphic: $text{p-lim}(1) = 1$, $text{p-lim}(Cx_n) = Ctext{p-lim}(x_n)$ (for some $C in {0, 1}$), $text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $oplus$ is the "or" operator), and $text{p-lim}(x_n otimes y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) otimes text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $otimes$ is the "and" operator)

  • bounded: $text{p-inf}(x_n) leq text{p-lim}(x_n) leq text{p-sup}(x_n)$

  • non-principality: deletion of a finite number of elements from $x_n$ should not change its $text{p-lim}$.


We do not know anything else about $text{p-lim}$, so a combination of these facts must be used to prove the required.



Note that $x_n$ will never be finite, since it is an indicator sequence which runs over all the natural numbers, hence $y_n$ will never be finite either. So non-principality is unlikely to be a useful tool. The supremum and infimum of every sequence of binary numbers which is not $1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 dots$ or $0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, dots$ is trivially $0$ and $1$ respectively, so it is unlikely that boundedness can be used as a tool.



Let us try to use the fact that $text{p-lim}$ is a homomorphism. Note that $y_n oplus x_n = y_n$, since $x_n subset y_n$ (in other words, $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$, while $x_k = 0 Rightarrow (y_k = 1 vee y_k = 0)$). Then:



begin{align*}
&quad;; x_n oplus y_n = y_n \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow 1 oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&{text{1 is the zero of $oplus$}} \
&Rightarrow 1 = text{p-lim}(y_n)
end{align*}





Is this proof correct? The following assumptions, I think, will need confirmation:




  • On the space of binary numbers, is it okay to assume that $oplus, otimes$ are the analogues of $+, times$, for the homomorphism property? I think it should be okay, because: 1) it makes things work out nicely (I think I can use similar logic to show that some of the other ultrafilter properties hold for the $text{p-lim}$ over the binary numbers), and connects nicely to classical "predicate calculus" stuff; 2) $oplus, otimes$ can also be thought of as "addition/multiplication $mathbb{Z}/2$")










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 5:34












  • $begingroup$
    It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 23:07










  • $begingroup$
    @HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Jan 31 at 18:45
















1












$begingroup$


I am working through this post from Terry Tao's blog.



Problem: Prove that if a binary (i.e. consisting of $0$ and $1$, or $top$ and $bot$) sequence $x_n$ is such that $text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$, then any sequence $y_n$ containing $x_n$ has $text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$.



My attempt at a proof. We know the following facts regarding $text{p-lim}$:




  • homomorphic: $text{p-lim}(1) = 1$, $text{p-lim}(Cx_n) = Ctext{p-lim}(x_n)$ (for some $C in {0, 1}$), $text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $oplus$ is the "or" operator), and $text{p-lim}(x_n otimes y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) otimes text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $otimes$ is the "and" operator)

  • bounded: $text{p-inf}(x_n) leq text{p-lim}(x_n) leq text{p-sup}(x_n)$

  • non-principality: deletion of a finite number of elements from $x_n$ should not change its $text{p-lim}$.


We do not know anything else about $text{p-lim}$, so a combination of these facts must be used to prove the required.



Note that $x_n$ will never be finite, since it is an indicator sequence which runs over all the natural numbers, hence $y_n$ will never be finite either. So non-principality is unlikely to be a useful tool. The supremum and infimum of every sequence of binary numbers which is not $1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 dots$ or $0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, dots$ is trivially $0$ and $1$ respectively, so it is unlikely that boundedness can be used as a tool.



Let us try to use the fact that $text{p-lim}$ is a homomorphism. Note that $y_n oplus x_n = y_n$, since $x_n subset y_n$ (in other words, $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$, while $x_k = 0 Rightarrow (y_k = 1 vee y_k = 0)$). Then:



begin{align*}
&quad;; x_n oplus y_n = y_n \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow 1 oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&{text{1 is the zero of $oplus$}} \
&Rightarrow 1 = text{p-lim}(y_n)
end{align*}





Is this proof correct? The following assumptions, I think, will need confirmation:




  • On the space of binary numbers, is it okay to assume that $oplus, otimes$ are the analogues of $+, times$, for the homomorphism property? I think it should be okay, because: 1) it makes things work out nicely (I think I can use similar logic to show that some of the other ultrafilter properties hold for the $text{p-lim}$ over the binary numbers), and connects nicely to classical "predicate calculus" stuff; 2) $oplus, otimes$ can also be thought of as "addition/multiplication $mathbb{Z}/2$")










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 5:34












  • $begingroup$
    It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 23:07










  • $begingroup$
    @HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Jan 31 at 18:45














1












1








1





$begingroup$


I am working through this post from Terry Tao's blog.



Problem: Prove that if a binary (i.e. consisting of $0$ and $1$, or $top$ and $bot$) sequence $x_n$ is such that $text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$, then any sequence $y_n$ containing $x_n$ has $text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$.



My attempt at a proof. We know the following facts regarding $text{p-lim}$:




  • homomorphic: $text{p-lim}(1) = 1$, $text{p-lim}(Cx_n) = Ctext{p-lim}(x_n)$ (for some $C in {0, 1}$), $text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $oplus$ is the "or" operator), and $text{p-lim}(x_n otimes y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) otimes text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $otimes$ is the "and" operator)

  • bounded: $text{p-inf}(x_n) leq text{p-lim}(x_n) leq text{p-sup}(x_n)$

  • non-principality: deletion of a finite number of elements from $x_n$ should not change its $text{p-lim}$.


We do not know anything else about $text{p-lim}$, so a combination of these facts must be used to prove the required.



Note that $x_n$ will never be finite, since it is an indicator sequence which runs over all the natural numbers, hence $y_n$ will never be finite either. So non-principality is unlikely to be a useful tool. The supremum and infimum of every sequence of binary numbers which is not $1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 dots$ or $0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, dots$ is trivially $0$ and $1$ respectively, so it is unlikely that boundedness can be used as a tool.



Let us try to use the fact that $text{p-lim}$ is a homomorphism. Note that $y_n oplus x_n = y_n$, since $x_n subset y_n$ (in other words, $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$, while $x_k = 0 Rightarrow (y_k = 1 vee y_k = 0)$). Then:



begin{align*}
&quad;; x_n oplus y_n = y_n \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow 1 oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&{text{1 is the zero of $oplus$}} \
&Rightarrow 1 = text{p-lim}(y_n)
end{align*}





Is this proof correct? The following assumptions, I think, will need confirmation:




  • On the space of binary numbers, is it okay to assume that $oplus, otimes$ are the analogues of $+, times$, for the homomorphism property? I think it should be okay, because: 1) it makes things work out nicely (I think I can use similar logic to show that some of the other ultrafilter properties hold for the $text{p-lim}$ over the binary numbers), and connects nicely to classical "predicate calculus" stuff; 2) $oplus, otimes$ can also be thought of as "addition/multiplication $mathbb{Z}/2$")










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I am working through this post from Terry Tao's blog.



Problem: Prove that if a binary (i.e. consisting of $0$ and $1$, or $top$ and $bot$) sequence $x_n$ is such that $text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$, then any sequence $y_n$ containing $x_n$ has $text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) = 1$.



My attempt at a proof. We know the following facts regarding $text{p-lim}$:




  • homomorphic: $text{p-lim}(1) = 1$, $text{p-lim}(Cx_n) = Ctext{p-lim}(x_n)$ (for some $C in {0, 1}$), $text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $oplus$ is the "or" operator), and $text{p-lim}(x_n otimes y_n) = text{p-lim}(x_n) otimes text{p-lim}(y_n)$ (where $otimes$ is the "and" operator)

  • bounded: $text{p-inf}(x_n) leq text{p-lim}(x_n) leq text{p-sup}(x_n)$

  • non-principality: deletion of a finite number of elements from $x_n$ should not change its $text{p-lim}$.


We do not know anything else about $text{p-lim}$, so a combination of these facts must be used to prove the required.



Note that $x_n$ will never be finite, since it is an indicator sequence which runs over all the natural numbers, hence $y_n$ will never be finite either. So non-principality is unlikely to be a useful tool. The supremum and infimum of every sequence of binary numbers which is not $1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 dots$ or $0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, dots$ is trivially $0$ and $1$ respectively, so it is unlikely that boundedness can be used as a tool.



Let us try to use the fact that $text{p-lim}$ is a homomorphism. Note that $y_n oplus x_n = y_n$, since $x_n subset y_n$ (in other words, $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$, while $x_k = 0 Rightarrow (y_k = 1 vee y_k = 0)$). Then:



begin{align*}
&quad;; x_n oplus y_n = y_n \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n oplus y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow text{p-lim}(x_n) oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&Rightarrow 1 oplus text{p-lim}(y_n) = text{p-lim}(y_n) \
&{text{1 is the zero of $oplus$}} \
&Rightarrow 1 = text{p-lim}(y_n)
end{align*}





Is this proof correct? The following assumptions, I think, will need confirmation:




  • On the space of binary numbers, is it okay to assume that $oplus, otimes$ are the analogues of $+, times$, for the homomorphism property? I think it should be okay, because: 1) it makes things work out nicely (I think I can use similar logic to show that some of the other ultrafilter properties hold for the $text{p-lim}$ over the binary numbers), and connects nicely to classical "predicate calculus" stuff; 2) $oplus, otimes$ can also be thought of as "addition/multiplication $mathbb{Z}/2$")







limits proof-verification filters






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jan 31 at 18:46







user89

















asked Jan 27 at 6:47









user89user89

5831647




5831647












  • $begingroup$
    What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 5:34












  • $begingroup$
    It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 23:07










  • $begingroup$
    @HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Jan 31 at 18:45


















  • $begingroup$
    What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 5:34












  • $begingroup$
    It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Jan 30 at 23:07










  • $begingroup$
    @HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Jan 31 at 18:45
















$begingroup$
What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Jan 30 at 5:34






$begingroup$
What do you mean by $(y_n)$ "containing" $(x_n)$? Sequences are functions, not sets.. It seems you mean $y_n le x_n$ for all $n$?
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Jan 30 at 5:34














$begingroup$
It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Jan 30 at 23:07




$begingroup$
It seems that you mean by "$x_n subset y_n$" that $y_k le x_k$ for all $k$; is that true? In the subset interpretation Tao gives the latter means that the subset of $omega$ associated with $y$ is a subset of the one asssociated with $x$, so inclusion the other way around.... You seem confused.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Jan 30 at 23:07












$begingroup$
@HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
$endgroup$
– user89
Jan 31 at 18:45




$begingroup$
@HennoBrandsma by $x_n$ being contained in $y_n$, I mean: $x_k = 1 Rightarrow y_k = 1$
$endgroup$
– user89
Jan 31 at 18:45










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















0












$begingroup$

You can go about it in two ways, which come down to the same thing. If we have a $p$-lim for sequences with values $0$ and $1$ we can identify a sequence $x=(x_n)$ with a subset $A(x) subseteq omega$ where $n in A(x)$ iff $x_n =1$ (using characteristic functions, in other words, or indicator sequences as Tao calls them). As $p$-$lim(x_n) in {0,1}$ as well, as he also shows, we have that a $p$-lim defines a non-principal ultrafilter $mathcal{F}$ on the powerset of $omega$: $A in mathcal{F}$ iff the indicator sequence $chi_A$ has $p$-$lim(chi_A)=1$. The monotonicity property you mention follows immediately from Tao's monotonicity principle: if two Boolean sequences $x,y$ obey: $forall k: x_k =1 implies y_k=1$, we see that $A(x) subseteq A(y)$ and as $p$-$lim(x)=1$ so $A(x) in mathcal{F}$ we have $A(y) in mathcal{F}$ by monotonicity of ultrafilters, and so $p$-$lim(y)=1$ as well.



To see the monotonicity of the ultrafilter (which Tao doesn't show) is to use the homomorphism properties. "$x$ is contained in $y$" (or $A(x) subseteq A(y)$) in your definition is equivalent to the identity $1-x+xy=1$ or $xy-x=x(y-1)=0$ (i.e. this holds for all $k$, as reals). This identity is preserved by $p$-$lim$ by its homomorphism property:



$$ptext{ -}lim(x)left(1-ptext{ -}lim(y)right) = 0$$



from which it follows that $ptext{ -}lim(x)=1$ implies $ptext{-}lim(y)=1$ which is what we needed.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Feb 1 at 3:47












  • $begingroup$
    @user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 1 at 5:28











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3089213%2fif-x-n-is-a-0-1-sequence-such-that-textp-limx-n-1-then-any-0-1-seque%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









0












$begingroup$

You can go about it in two ways, which come down to the same thing. If we have a $p$-lim for sequences with values $0$ and $1$ we can identify a sequence $x=(x_n)$ with a subset $A(x) subseteq omega$ where $n in A(x)$ iff $x_n =1$ (using characteristic functions, in other words, or indicator sequences as Tao calls them). As $p$-$lim(x_n) in {0,1}$ as well, as he also shows, we have that a $p$-lim defines a non-principal ultrafilter $mathcal{F}$ on the powerset of $omega$: $A in mathcal{F}$ iff the indicator sequence $chi_A$ has $p$-$lim(chi_A)=1$. The monotonicity property you mention follows immediately from Tao's monotonicity principle: if two Boolean sequences $x,y$ obey: $forall k: x_k =1 implies y_k=1$, we see that $A(x) subseteq A(y)$ and as $p$-$lim(x)=1$ so $A(x) in mathcal{F}$ we have $A(y) in mathcal{F}$ by monotonicity of ultrafilters, and so $p$-$lim(y)=1$ as well.



To see the monotonicity of the ultrafilter (which Tao doesn't show) is to use the homomorphism properties. "$x$ is contained in $y$" (or $A(x) subseteq A(y)$) in your definition is equivalent to the identity $1-x+xy=1$ or $xy-x=x(y-1)=0$ (i.e. this holds for all $k$, as reals). This identity is preserved by $p$-$lim$ by its homomorphism property:



$$ptext{ -}lim(x)left(1-ptext{ -}lim(y)right) = 0$$



from which it follows that $ptext{ -}lim(x)=1$ implies $ptext{-}lim(y)=1$ which is what we needed.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Feb 1 at 3:47












  • $begingroup$
    @user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 1 at 5:28
















0












$begingroup$

You can go about it in two ways, which come down to the same thing. If we have a $p$-lim for sequences with values $0$ and $1$ we can identify a sequence $x=(x_n)$ with a subset $A(x) subseteq omega$ where $n in A(x)$ iff $x_n =1$ (using characteristic functions, in other words, or indicator sequences as Tao calls them). As $p$-$lim(x_n) in {0,1}$ as well, as he also shows, we have that a $p$-lim defines a non-principal ultrafilter $mathcal{F}$ on the powerset of $omega$: $A in mathcal{F}$ iff the indicator sequence $chi_A$ has $p$-$lim(chi_A)=1$. The monotonicity property you mention follows immediately from Tao's monotonicity principle: if two Boolean sequences $x,y$ obey: $forall k: x_k =1 implies y_k=1$, we see that $A(x) subseteq A(y)$ and as $p$-$lim(x)=1$ so $A(x) in mathcal{F}$ we have $A(y) in mathcal{F}$ by monotonicity of ultrafilters, and so $p$-$lim(y)=1$ as well.



To see the monotonicity of the ultrafilter (which Tao doesn't show) is to use the homomorphism properties. "$x$ is contained in $y$" (or $A(x) subseteq A(y)$) in your definition is equivalent to the identity $1-x+xy=1$ or $xy-x=x(y-1)=0$ (i.e. this holds for all $k$, as reals). This identity is preserved by $p$-$lim$ by its homomorphism property:



$$ptext{ -}lim(x)left(1-ptext{ -}lim(y)right) = 0$$



from which it follows that $ptext{ -}lim(x)=1$ implies $ptext{-}lim(y)=1$ which is what we needed.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Feb 1 at 3:47












  • $begingroup$
    @user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 1 at 5:28














0












0








0





$begingroup$

You can go about it in two ways, which come down to the same thing. If we have a $p$-lim for sequences with values $0$ and $1$ we can identify a sequence $x=(x_n)$ with a subset $A(x) subseteq omega$ where $n in A(x)$ iff $x_n =1$ (using characteristic functions, in other words, or indicator sequences as Tao calls them). As $p$-$lim(x_n) in {0,1}$ as well, as he also shows, we have that a $p$-lim defines a non-principal ultrafilter $mathcal{F}$ on the powerset of $omega$: $A in mathcal{F}$ iff the indicator sequence $chi_A$ has $p$-$lim(chi_A)=1$. The monotonicity property you mention follows immediately from Tao's monotonicity principle: if two Boolean sequences $x,y$ obey: $forall k: x_k =1 implies y_k=1$, we see that $A(x) subseteq A(y)$ and as $p$-$lim(x)=1$ so $A(x) in mathcal{F}$ we have $A(y) in mathcal{F}$ by monotonicity of ultrafilters, and so $p$-$lim(y)=1$ as well.



To see the monotonicity of the ultrafilter (which Tao doesn't show) is to use the homomorphism properties. "$x$ is contained in $y$" (or $A(x) subseteq A(y)$) in your definition is equivalent to the identity $1-x+xy=1$ or $xy-x=x(y-1)=0$ (i.e. this holds for all $k$, as reals). This identity is preserved by $p$-$lim$ by its homomorphism property:



$$ptext{ -}lim(x)left(1-ptext{ -}lim(y)right) = 0$$



from which it follows that $ptext{ -}lim(x)=1$ implies $ptext{-}lim(y)=1$ which is what we needed.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



You can go about it in two ways, which come down to the same thing. If we have a $p$-lim for sequences with values $0$ and $1$ we can identify a sequence $x=(x_n)$ with a subset $A(x) subseteq omega$ where $n in A(x)$ iff $x_n =1$ (using characteristic functions, in other words, or indicator sequences as Tao calls them). As $p$-$lim(x_n) in {0,1}$ as well, as he also shows, we have that a $p$-lim defines a non-principal ultrafilter $mathcal{F}$ on the powerset of $omega$: $A in mathcal{F}$ iff the indicator sequence $chi_A$ has $p$-$lim(chi_A)=1$. The monotonicity property you mention follows immediately from Tao's monotonicity principle: if two Boolean sequences $x,y$ obey: $forall k: x_k =1 implies y_k=1$, we see that $A(x) subseteq A(y)$ and as $p$-$lim(x)=1$ so $A(x) in mathcal{F}$ we have $A(y) in mathcal{F}$ by monotonicity of ultrafilters, and so $p$-$lim(y)=1$ as well.



To see the monotonicity of the ultrafilter (which Tao doesn't show) is to use the homomorphism properties. "$x$ is contained in $y$" (or $A(x) subseteq A(y)$) in your definition is equivalent to the identity $1-x+xy=1$ or $xy-x=x(y-1)=0$ (i.e. this holds for all $k$, as reals). This identity is preserved by $p$-$lim$ by its homomorphism property:



$$ptext{ -}lim(x)left(1-ptext{ -}lim(y)right) = 0$$



from which it follows that $ptext{ -}lim(x)=1$ implies $ptext{-}lim(y)=1$ which is what we needed.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Jan 31 at 23:41

























answered Jan 31 at 23:18









Henno BrandsmaHenno Brandsma

114k348123




114k348123












  • $begingroup$
    Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Feb 1 at 3:47












  • $begingroup$
    @user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 1 at 5:28


















  • $begingroup$
    Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
    $endgroup$
    – user89
    Feb 1 at 3:47












  • $begingroup$
    @user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
    $endgroup$
    – Henno Brandsma
    Feb 1 at 5:28
















$begingroup$
Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
$endgroup$
– user89
Feb 1 at 3:47






$begingroup$
Can you comment on whether my proof approach was okay or not?
$endgroup$
– user89
Feb 1 at 3:47














$begingroup$
@user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Feb 1 at 5:28




$begingroup$
@user89 You have to prove separately that $oplus$ is preserved. I do think it's true, as it can be defined in terms of $+,cdot$ on the reals, when restricted to Boolean sequences, so do that. And you need to justify too that $x$ contained in $y$ iff $x oplus y = y$. I think the equivalence is not true.
$endgroup$
– Henno Brandsma
Feb 1 at 5:28


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3089213%2fif-x-n-is-a-0-1-sequence-such-that-textp-limx-n-1-then-any-0-1-seque%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

MongoDB - Not Authorized To Execute Command

How to fix TextFormField cause rebuild widget in Flutter

in spring boot 2.1 many test slices are not allowed anymore due to multiple @BootstrapWith